MUSLIM
INTELLECTUAL
Reader in Arabic, University of
Edinburgh
EDINBURGH
At the University Press
© 1963 W. Montgomery Watt
EDINBURGH UNIVERSITY PRESS
22 George Square, Edinburgh
ISBN 0 85224 127 5
North America
Aldine Publishing Company
529 South Wabash Avenue, Chicago
Printed in Great Britain by
R. & R. Clark Ltd., Edinburgh
Reprinted 1971
Set in 12 point Garamond and
OCRed
by
for
CONTENTS
Chapter One
THE FUNCTION OF THE INTELLECTUAL 1
Chapter Two
THE WORLD OF AL-GHAZALI
1The Political Background 7
2 The Religious and Intellectual
Background 14
Chapter Three
THE ENCOUNTER WITH PHILOSOPHY
1 The Philosophical Movement in the Islamic World
2 The Social Relevance of Philosophical Ideas
3 Al-Ghazalis Period of Scepticism
4 The Inconsistency of the Philosophers
5 The Introduction of Logic into Theology
Chapter Four
TRUTH FROM THE CHARISMATIC LEADER
1 Isma`ilite Doctrine in its
Political Setting
2 The Intellectual Defence of
Sunnism
Chapter Five
THE REAPPRAISAL OF THEOLOGY
1 The Achievements of Islamic Theology 88
2 Theologians and Governments 98
3 Al-Ghazalis Critique of the
Scholar-Jurists 108
4 Dogmatic Theology from a New
Standpoint 117
Chapter Six
THE BITTERNESS OF
WORLDLY SUCCESS
1 The Sufi Movement 128
2 The Crisis of 1095 133
3 Life as a Sufi 143
4 The Revival of the Religious
Sciences 151
Chapter Seven
THE INTELLECTUAL BASIS OF THE REVIVED COMMUNITY
1 The Intellectual Class and the
Conception of Knowledge
2 The New Intellectual
Structure of the Community
Chapter Eight
THE ACHIEVEMENT
1 The Tension between Philosophy
and Theology 173
2 The Batinite Challenge 175
3 The Tension between the
Islamic Sciences and Sufism 176
Excursus 181
Notes 187
Chronological Table; Bibliography
Index 207
THE
difficulty of writing about al-Ghazali is well illustrated by the various
comments and criticisms that have been made of the works by Julius Obermann, A.
J. Wensinck, Margaret Smith and Farid Jabre. The difficulty is due to the great
volume of his writings, to the fact that books were ascribed to him that were
definitely not by him, and to the changes in his outlook which occurred during
the course of his life. When the growth and development of his outlook is
combined with the lack of complete agreement about which works are unauthentic,
scholars are presented with some peculiarly intractable problems before they
can properly begin the study of al-Ghazalis thought. Yet the subject is one
that is well worth attempting. Al-Ghazali has been acclaimed as the greatest
Muslim after Muhammad, and is certainly one of the greatest. His outlook, too,
is closer than that of many Muslims to the outlook of modern Europe and America,
so that he is more easily comprehensible to us. Thus there is here a great
challenge to scholarship.
The present study of the struggle
and achievement of al-Ghazali does not attempt to take up that challenge in its
entirety, but only to look at his life and thought as a whole within the
context of the times in which he lived. I have tried to write in such a way
that the book could be read by general sociologists as well as by students of
Islam, but this means that Islamists will find an undue neglect of detail. In
defence I would make the plea that it is necessary to look at the picture as a
whole before we can see at what points further detailed study is needed. The
general standpoint from which I write is that of the sociology of knowledge-a
discipline which,. though still in its infancy, is characteristic of our age
and an expression of its spirit. Since practically nothing has been written
about the Islamic world from this standpoint, I have found it necessary to
re-examine and reassess much of the previous history of Islamic thought. This
re-assessment had largely been made, and the relevant sections of this book
written, before I began Islamic
Philosophy and Theology.
I have to thank my eldest daughter for helping with the Index and my wife for correcting proofs as well as putting up with the vagaries of a husband wrapped up in the writing of a book.
W.
MONTGOMERY WATT
Edinburgh,
November 1962
I
THE
FUNCTION OF THE INTELLECTUAL
THIS book arises out of a concern felt by many
intellectuals. In the desperate predicament of the world in which they live can
they as intellectuals make any special contribution to saving it from the
destruction which threatens? It was once thought that ideas controlled the
course of history, and there are many remnants of this belief; but on the whole
it is now discredited. Many men, instead, tend to acknowledge the dominion of
economic and material factors, whether regretfully or eagerly. If ideas are
powerless, then the intellectual, as the bearer of ideas, has no important
functions.
In Islam and the Integration of Society I tried to show that, while economic and material factors
determine the setting of mans life, ideational factors direct his responses to
the situations in which he found himself. Corresponding to this function of
ideas in the life of society will be the function of the intellectuals as the
persons primarily responsible for dealing with ideas. The present study is an
attempt to show in detail what this handling of ideas amounts to, and the
method is to examine the life and thought of one of the greatest intellectuals
of Islamic society, al-Ghazali.
It is convenient to speak of the intellectuals or
intelligentsia as if they constituted a single class. Yet as soon as one begins
to consider them closely, they appear to be manifold in their variety. There
are all those concerned with the handing on of ideas to other people, whether
school-teachers, university professors, journalists, broadcasters or writers of
books. There are all those
concerned with the application of ideas to detailed
situations; almost everyone does this to some extent, but we might think here
specially of politicians and civil servants. Even when, setting aside the
transmission and application of ideas, we confine ourselves to the creative handling
of ideas, there would still appear to be three aspects: instrumental,
systematizing and intuitive.
(a) The instrumental intellectual
par excellence is the scientist, who
investigates our environment and thereby increases our control over it. Even the
pure scientist, who does not think of the practical applications of his work,
is in fact performing this function for his society. At the present time men
are developing the social sciences, and thereby increasing the possibilities of
controlling society and other men. (b) Representatives of the systematizing
trend are the philosopher, the philosophically-minded scientist, the
theologian, the legal theorist, and perhaps the historian where he is finding
general rules implicit in particular events. (c) The intuitive intellectual may
be said to be concerned with the values acknowledged in a society and their
basis in reality. A prophetic leader like Muhammad, who directed far reaching
social and political movements, is a good example of the intuitive intellectual.
But in the same group would also come poets and other litterateurs, and
likewise historians and humanistic scholars. The politician is placed here in
so far as he is dealing with lofty and important issues.2
While these three aspects are
clearly distinct, they are probably seldom found in their pure state.
Systematization is usually a type of activity that does not proceed
automatically but requires an element of intuition. There may even be an
element of intuition lurking in the results of the scientist, especially of the
social scientist. The present study is chiefly concerned with the ideas which
are fundamental to the whole life of Islamic
society, and these belong
primarily to the intuitive aspect. Because of the intermingling of the aspects
in actual life, however, it will not be necessary to label particular men as
intuitives or systematizers. It is also to be noted that in so far as the
response to a situation is intuitive it is partly unconscious; the intellectual
need not be fully aware either of that to which he is responding or of the
precise manner of his response to it.
The phrase bearers of ideas
suggests a measure of passivity, but the intuitive intellectual is essentially
creative. Such creativity cannot be avoided. A society is a living thing, and
the situation to which it has to respond is constantly changing. Even where the
economic and material framework of its life is stable, there is a constant
movement of social adjustment which goes to constitute the given situation at
any time. The ideational basis of a relatively stable society has a certain
fixity, but it is also always undergoing modification in detail, even if only
in respect of emphasis. This modification is the work of the intuitive
intellectual. Ideas, too, even when they remain ostensibly unchanged, may
through material and social changes come to fulfill a different role in the
life of society. The outstanding case of this is where ideas, which were
originally sound and appropriate_ to the time, become ideological (in the
technical sense) through being used to bolster up a sectional privilege which
in the interests of society as a whole ought to be abolished. An example in the
field of religion is the case of the Pharisees in the New Testament. Their
ideas were substantially the same as those of the religious leaders of the Jews
some two hundred years earlier. In the earlier period the ideas were an
appropriate bastion for the defence of the Jewish religion against the cultural
attack of Hellenism; but in the later period they had become a vehicle for the
self-satisfied pride, complacency and even hypocrisy which we now associate
with Pharisaism.
It is not necessary here to try
to classify all the types of adaptation that are required of intellectuals, but
only to notice that there are several different types. In so far as the society
is a homogeneous one, the main types of adaptation will be to changed material
circumstances and to the changed social conditions arising out of the material
changes. The adaptation consists in the modification of the ideational basis of
the society so that activity in accordance with the new ideational basis is a
more satisfactory response to the existing situation. A society such as that of
the Islamic world, however, is not homogeneous. Besides the different social
classes there are-often cutting across class divisions-groups from divergent
cultural backgrounds. Here part of the work of the intellectual is to attempt
to find an ideational synthesis which will increase the integration in the society
and decrease the tensions. Ideally such an ideational synthesis is a complex of
ideas in which each group can find those elements in which it is chiefly
interested, and find them in a form which does not offend other groups. The
intellectual can only achieve this modification and adaptation in so far as he
is himself involved in his society and its tensions. Sometimes he can
deliberately bring about such involvement-as al-Ghazali did when he set about
studying the views of the philosophers and the Batinites and genuinely trying
to appreciate the truth in them. Where there is tension between two sections of
a society, there is a place for intellectuals in each section; but the most
satisfying and lasting work for an intellectual would appear to be in maintaining
a certain detachment from the contending factions.
A study such as the
present cannot be completely objective, since the writers own attitude to
religion enters into his assessment and presentation of the facts. The best way
to minimize the harmful effects of this subjective bias is to try to make
explicit what ones attitude is.
So far as I am aware, then, the following three points
define the attitude to religion on which this investigation is based:
(1) Human life has
significance, meaning or transcendent value. The word transcendent here
indicates that this value is not negated by death or transiency, not even by
the disappearance of human life from the solar system.
(2) This
transcendent value is normally given what maybe called an ontological basis.
That is, it is demonstrated, or perhaps merely asserted, that reality is such
that the value is indeed transcendent; for example, Marxists assert that the
dialectic of history inevitably leads to the classless society. Whether this
ontological basis is true or false, and whether it is meaningful here to
speak about truth and falsehood, are questions belonging to another discipline.
All that is assumed in this study is that the ontological basis is a set of
ideas which has sociological functions. It might be said, of course, that such
an assumption implies that the ontological basis has a degree or measure of
truth.
(3) The language in which the
transcendent value and the ontological basis are expressed is closer to that
of poetry than to that of science. In pointing or hinting at the nature of
reality it is necessarily vaguer than language based on sense-experience. This
makes it possible for different religions and sects to refer to the same (or
almost the same) aspect of reality in ways that are superficially
contradictory. (The extent to which such contradictions are based on
pre-religious categories of thinking is a subject requiring further
investigation.)
II
THE WORLD OF AL-GHAZALI
I THE POLITICAL BACKGROUND
IN a sense the background of the
life of any individual is the whole previous history of his civilization. For
an understanding of al-Ghazali it will be sufficient to glance briefly at the
history of the Islamic empire or caliphate from the death of Muhammad in 632 to
the birth of al-Ghazali in 1058. In these four centuries four main phases may
be distinguished, which may be labelled: conquests; conversion; disintegration;
reconstitution. These phases follow one another chronologically, but overlap to
some extent.
(1) The Conquests. As Muhammad lay on his deathbed
in Medina an expedition was being assembled on the outskirts of the town whose
task was in fact to open the way for the conquest of Syria. For the next two
years, however, the Muslim leaders were busy suppressing revolts in Arabia, but
in the following ten years the small state with its centre at Medina wrested
the rich provinces of Syria and Egypt from the Byzantine empire and that of
Iraq from the Persian empire, besides sending the latter reeling to
destruction. A hundred years after Muhammads death the sway of his successor
extended from north of the Pyrenees, through North Africa and the Fertile
Crescent to Central Asia (Transoxiana) and the Punjab.
The effective control of these
vast territories after the amazingly rapid conquest was made possible by the
simplicity of the central organization. The Arabs constituted themselves into a
vast army. At the extremities of their domains they had the help of auxiliaries
from such peoples as the Berbers, but otherwise the army of Arabs did all the
fighting and all the garrison-work. The local administrations were taken over
and continued to function much as before. All that the Arab provincial
governors had to do was to have direct supervision over the army and then to see
that the non-Arab local administration was effective and handed over the due
taxes.
The head of
this state was called the caliph or successor (sc. of Muhammad), and had
inherited the latters administrative but not his prophetic functions; the
state is correspondingly known as the caliphate. From the description given it
will be seen that it is essentially an Arab-Muslim military aristocracy; or
rather, only those who are Arabs and Muslims are full citizens, serving in the
army and in return drawing an annual stipend. The non-Muslims were related to
the Muslim government not as individuals but as groups, later known as millets,
and usually with a religious basis; e.g. the Christians of Jerusalem or the
Jews of Iraq. Such a group had internal autonomy under its religious head, who
was responsible to the government for handing over the taxes. Since it was a
matter of honour for the ruler to make the official protection of such groups
effective, there was practically no religious persecution. Yet the suggestion that
these protected persons were second-class citizens meant that there was a
constant pressure on them to become Muslims. On the whole the system has worked
well and made life tolerable for millions; but it has tended to freeze small
groups and prevent their assimilation in the larger whole except at a very slow
rate (by conversions to Islam). The present troubles with minorities in the
Middle East are largely due to the breakdown of the millet system of the
Ottoman empire.
(2) Conversion. Islam
was by tradition a missionary religion, and was, at least implicitly, of
universal validity. Because of its Arabic origin, however, there was a tendency
to think of it as primarily for Arabs. This tendency was reinforced during the
first century of the caliphate by the desire of the Arab Muslims to retain
their privileged position as first-class citizens. Little effort was made in
the early decades to convert non-Arabs to Islam. When non-Arabs insisted on
becoming Muslims, whatever their motives may have been, they had to be attached
to Arab tribes as clients. This still had a suggestion of inferiority. As the
number of non-Arab Muslims increased, their discontent with their status and
demand for equality was one of the factors behind the movement which replaced
the Umayyad caliphs of Damascus (who had ruled from 660 to 750) by the `Abbasid
caliphs of Baghdad. This change was not simply a change of dynasty; it was a
change of the basis of the caliphate. The body politic was now more explicitly
based on Islamic principles and regarded as a charismatic community; and all
Muslims, whether Arab or not, were full citizens. The establishment of the
`Abbasid caliphate thus reflected the fact that many nonArabs had been
converted to Islam.
Yet the change of dynasty also
meant in various ways a return to Persian ideas of autocratic government. Under
the Umayyads power had been shared between the new Islamic aristocracy (who
received higher stipends because they or their ancestors had become Muslims at
an early date) and sections of the old Arab aristocracy. At many points actions
had been based on traditional Arab political ideas, derived from experience
with tribes and confederations of tribes; but in several ways this was
unsatisfactory, and unsuited for a vast empire. Under the earlier `Abbasids
power was almost exclusively in the hands of the caliph and his court. Since
membership of the court was virtually in the gift of the caliph, this meant
that power was in the hands of the caliph and one or two other men, such as the
Barmakid viziers; how far the caliph had to share his power depended on his
strength and capacity for controlling affairs. Within the court circle, that
is, within the ruling institution, there was practically no check on the
autocratic decisions of the caliph; and contemporary chronicles depict a naked
struggle for power in which nothing was barred. On the other hand, the
relations between the ruling institution and those ruled were largely
determined by Islamic principles as stated in the Shai a or revealed law. The
general acceptance of Islamic principles outside the court circle produced
during the next century or two a high degree of homogeneity in the vast and
varied empire.
(3) Disintegration. After the first enthusiasm had
waned the `Abbasids found it increasingly difficult to exercise effective
control over their domains. Provincial governors had to be given large powers,
including the command of considerable armies. If they disliked some order from
the caliph, they could hardly be forced to obey it. They tended to present the
caliph with a series of faits accomplis, such
as the extension of the boundaries of their province, which he was obliged to
ratify. At length demands came that a son should succeed to the governorship,
and the caliph had to accede. Thus there came into being local dynasties, for
all practical purposes autonomous, but making a formal acknowledgement of the
supremacy of the caliph. This description is specially applicable to the east,
where there are four dynasties which deserve to be mentioned.
(a) Tahirids. Five men (four
generations) of the Tahirid family maintained themselves as governors of
Khurasan from 820 to 872. From the standpoint of the present study it is worth
noting that the Tahirids, by making Nishapur their capital, gave a fillip to
its development as an intellectual and cultural centre. Their downfall resulted
not from any action of the caliph but from military defeat by the first of the
Saffarids.
(b) Saffarids.
Three men of the Saflaarid family, starting shortly before 868 from the
governorship of Sijistan (roughly southern Afghanistan), extended their rule
(by 872) to most of southern and eastern Persia up to the Oxus, and maintained
themselves there until about 903.
(c) Samanids. The
Samanid family is reckoned as having ruled from 874 to 999, and has a complex
history which need not be described here. The chief basis of their power was
Transoxiana, and their eastern capital, Bukhara, became a literary and cultural
centre of great brilliance? After they had wrested Khurasan from the Saffarids
(900-910) Nishapur became their second capital, not far behind Bukhara in the
splendour of its intellectual life.
(d) Ghaznavids. The
Ghaznavid dynasty (976-1186) was of Turkish race, being descended from officers
in the Samanid armies. Subuktigin became governor in the mountain town of
Ghazna (about a hundred miles south of Kabul in Afghanistan), and extended his
power both towards India and into eastern Persia. His son, Mahmud of Ghazna (regnabat 998-1030), repudiated
Samanid suzerainty, was appointed governor of Khurasan and Ghazna directly by
the caliph, and made great conquests in India. Soon after the death of Mahmud,
however, the dynasty began to be deprived by the Seljuqs of its domains in
Persia and Transoxiana, so that from about 1050 its rule was restricted to
Afghanistan and India.
Further west there were small dynasties which developed from provincial governorships and continued to acknowledge the caliph of Baghdad. In the west, however, there were also actual losses of territory. A few years after the overthrow of the Umayyad caliph by the `Abbasids, a member of the Umayyad family became independent ruler of Spain, though without claiming to be caliph. Such a claim was first made by the Fatimids, a dynasty which established itself first in Tunisia in 909, and then in 969 transferred the seat of its power to Egypt. The Fatimid rulers claimed to be the rightful caliphs of the whole Islamic world, and sent emissaries into the Abbasid domains to preach revolution. No more need be said about the Fatimids here, since their propaganda (also known as Ismailite or Batinite) became a major concern for al-Ghazali (chapter IV).
(4) Reconstitution. The word reconstitution is not
altogether satisfactory as a description of the fourth phase of the caliphate,
but it is convenient to have a single word. In this phase the caliph loses most
of his remaining power, though he retains his position as a figurehead with
certain official functions and dignities. Real power passed into the hands of a
series of warlords, who eventually came to have the title of sultan. The
first of these war-lords was Ibn-Raiq, who entered Baghdad at the head of an
army in 936 and simply took over the machinery of government from the caliphs
vizier. As a Muslim historian puts it: 3
From this time the power of the viziers ceased. The
vizier no longer had control of the provinces, the bureaux or the departments;
he had merely the title of vizier, and the right of appearing on ceremonial
days at the Palace in black with sword and belt.
Ibn-Raiq held this lofty position for less than two
years, but in 945 Baghdad was captured by the Buwayhid (or Buyid) family-chiefs
of a warlike highland tribe from Daylam, at the south of the Caspian Sea-who
assumed the reins of government, and held them, though latterly with a
slackening grip, until 1055. Their direct rule extended over Iraq and a large
part of Persia, but provinces were entrusted to different members of the
family, and these did not always see eye to eye.
The Buwayhids eventually fell
before another family of war-lords, the Seljuqs, who, supported by Turkish
tribesmen, first made themselves masters of Khurasan, and then in 1055
established themselves in Baghdad. At its widest extent their empire was much
greater than that of the Buwayhids, including Syria in the west and Transoxiana
and the whole of Persia in the east. This was the situation during the maturity
of al-Ghazali, but before his death in 1111 the central government was
weakening and it eventually disintegrated in 1157. This is as far as we need
follow the history of the caliphate.
This phase of reconstitution has various aspects. While in one way it was the end of the rule of the caliphs, in another way it was a restoration to the central government of the territories directly under the caliph. In this new central government the place of military power was more explicit. The early conquests had been made by a citizen army, but in course of time a citizen army was shown to have disadvantages. In any case, after conversion became frequent there were too many citizens for the army. In practice it was found more satisfactory to have mercenaries, though this meant that the officers of the mercenaries might have undue power. It was becoming clear that political power depended on military backing. Those who were successful in the struggle for power, like the Buwayhids and the Seljuqs, were groups of men-not isolated individuals-who had effective military support that was in part independent of monetary payments. Political power partly also depended on the acquiescence of the citizens, and this was gained by recognition of the Islamic basis of society-acknowledgement of the caliph, participation in worship on certain occasions, continuation of courts applying the Shari a. In major political decisions, however, and in the functioning of the court Islamic principles counted for nothing.
Despite this
apparently unsatisfactory state of affairs (at least from a theoretical
standpoint), the earlier part of the Seljuq period, especially the reigns of
Alp-Arslan (1063-72) and Malik-Shah (1072--92), was a time of comparative peace
and prosperity and of great cultural achievement 4 To this happy condition the
wise and efficient vizier of these two sultans, Nizam-al-Mulk, made an
outstanding contribution. Though nominally subordinate to the sultan, he was
practically all-powerful during these thirty years.
The religion of Islam in its earlier forms was adapted to
the social and intellectual needs of Mecca, Medina and Arabia.s But the
framework of material circumstances in which
it had to function even under the Umayyad caliphs was entirely different from
that of Muhammads closing years.
The first phase of development,
the conquests, quite apart from the effects on the subject peoples, involved a
vast social upheaval for the Arabs, that is, the Muslims. The old tribal and
clan system broke down; and, since it was through the tribe that a
mans life became meaningful, this led to a religious as well as a social
crisis. An important section of the Arabs dealt with this crisis by
substituting for the tribe the Islamic community. Life became meaningful for
them through membership of this community, since it was divinely founded and
was living in accordance with divinely-given mores. But the question of how to
deal with those who transgressed Gods commands proved intractable, and there
was much bitter argument before it was solved. In the end, however, a way was
found by which the whole community, despite the presence of sinners in it,
could be regarded as a saving sect, so that membership led to everlasting
bliss.6
The phase of conversion was a
piece of social adjustment following on the incorporation of vast territories
and their inhabitants in the Islamic empire. While some material self-interest
may have been a factor in conversion, the major factor was perhaps the
religious one-the attractiveness of the dynamic image of the Islamic community
as a charismatic one. Men felt they wanted really to belong to this, not just
to be loosely attached to it. The conception of the Islamic community as
charismatic, originally developed for Arab tribesmen whose tribe had broken
down, was further developed by the non-Arab Muslims. The distinctive
excellences of the community, especially its possession in the Shari`a of a
divinely-revealed law or rather set of practices, were linked with its
charismatic nature. Zeal for the charismatic community was an important factor
behind the incredible intellectual efforts expended in the elaboration of the
Shari`a.
In the course of elaborating the
Sharia something else was also done. Many of the new converts came from a
higher cultural level than the Arabs,
and naturally retained most of their culture. The pious scholars in whose hands
the $hari`a took shape not merely developed the principles found in the Quran
by adding to them the Traditions, that is, anecdotes about Muhammads words and
practices. Somehow or other, almost without any conscious deception, these
scholars managed to include among the Traditions much of the inherited wisdom
of the Middle East, transmitted through Christian, Jewish, Gnostic and other
sources. To the modern student this is all the more remarkable since Muslims
had a complex system of criticism of Traditions. Careful examination, however,
shows that this system was not aimed at ascertaining objective historical fact,
but at excluding the views of the eccentrics or lunatic fringe; and this it
largely succeeded in doing. The effect of systematic criticism was in fact to
stabilize the Islamic religion on a new ideational basis, namely, that amalgam
of Quranic principle, early practice and older lore which had come to be
accepted by the main body of Muslims round about the year 8oo. This amalgam, it
is to be noted, did not include the higher learning of the Middle East, such as
Greek philosophy and science; and the correct attitude to these foreign
sciences is one of the problems which al-Ghazali had to tackle.
By these ideational
developments the religion of Islam adapted itself with considerable adequacy to
the changes of the first two phases of conquest and conversion. The point where
its adaptation had been least adequate was within
the ruling institution. There Persian traditions of autocracy and the
unprincipled use of power had become dominant, even though in the relations of
the rulers to the ruled Islamic principles continued to be respected. In the
succeeding phases this impotence of Islamic principles in the topmost political
levels-so curious in view of Islams reputation in Europe of being a political
religion-contributed to the difficulties
of the intellectual class, and so to the major problem al-Ghazali had to solve.
It would be
convenient to describe with similar brevity the religious and ideational
repercussions of the third and fourth historical stages (of disintegration and
reconstitution); but unfortunately it is not possible. These repercussions have
not yet been properly investigated from the standpoint of this study. Moreover,
their investigation cannot be altogether separated from the problem of
al-Ghazali himself. As our understanding of this great man increases, we get
more light on what had been happening in the two centuries or so before his
birth. The economic, political, social, intellectual and religious happenings
of these centuries made the setting in which his life had to be lived. It is
part of the aim of this study to discover the salient features of that setting
and what had most contributed to making them what they were. At this
preliminary stage in the investigation three points may be noted.
(a) The standard Islamic
ideational system had taken root nearly everywhere. The war-lords were under
the necessity of recognizing it publicly in all their dealings with the
populace. Consequently the disintegration of the caliphate under the war-lords
led not to a diminution of Islamic intellectual culture but to its
encouragement in numerous local centres. Among the most vigorous of these
centres was Nishapur and the surrounding region, where al-Ghazalis early life
was spent.
(b) In the fourth phase, and also
in the third phase though less obviously, supreme rule belonged to superior
military force. This happened in a community which had hitherto been regarded
as charismatic or divinely-constituted. Did it mean that the community lost its
charismatic nature? Was the difficulty a serious one for the men of the time?
(c) Al-Ghazalis abandonment of
the standard career of a religious intellectual or scholar-jurist8 suggests
that there was something wrong with this career. Was it that it implied
subservience to godless rulers? Were the intellectuals trying to find the
significance of their lives in a framework in which Islam was irrelevant? Was
the difficulty that the Shari`a, whose ostensible purpose was to direct the
affairs of the body politic, obviously did not do this?
Al-Ghazali himself in his
autobiography speaks of four groups of men who were trying to find an adequate
response to the situation, and we can do no better than follow his guidance and
investigate the attitudes of these four groups: the philosophers; the Batinites
or Isma`ilites; the theologians (among whom we may make a further distinction
between Asharites and Hanbalites); the Sufis or mystics.
It remains to say a word about a
fifth possible response to the situation, a response in which al-Ghazali might
have been interested but in fact was not-the Persian renascence. Before the
Arab conquest of Persia the Zoroastrian clergy, to preserve their power as an
intellectual class, had become closely allied with the rulers and subservient
to them. In so doing they had largely become cutoff from the ordinary people.
When the phase of conversion began, therefore, it was not surprising that many
Persians became Muslims. The Persian Muslims had much to do with the
establishing of the `Abbasid dynasty, and in return the equality of all
Muslims, Arab and non-Arab, came to be generally recognized. After a time there
was a movement among the secretary class or civil service which maintained the
inferiority of the Arabs; but this Shu° ubite movement, as it was called, was
chiefly a literary movement, it would seem, without much political influence.
Other forms of Persian selfassertion are connected with Manichaeanism and with
certain sects of Shiite Islam.9
The real awakening of the Persian
spirit, however, did not come until after the phase of disintegration. Local or
provincial dynasties, especially the Samanids, were a focus for hopes and
aspirations. It should not be supposed, of course, that there already was a
Persian nationalism comparable to the nationalisms of the nineteenth century.
There was potentially something similar to these nationalisms, but it had to
become conscious of itself. The chief part in bringing about this national
selfawareness was played by Firdawsi (d. 1020-1025). His great epic, the Shah-ndma, welded many local traditions
into a unity and gave men of Persian descent a renewed enthusiasm for the
perennial mission of Iran-defence of civilization from the inroads of Turan,
the Turkish barbarians from the great steppes. This was a mission which could
be combined with membership of the Islamic empire, though one imagines that the
Persians would have found it difficult to go on for centuries serving these two
masters, Persian secular aggrandizement and the extension of Islam.
In favourable circumstances this
Persian movement might have grown and become of much political significance.
Circumstances were against it, however. Before Firdawsi had completed his great
poem the sun of the Samanids was setting, and in the ascendant was the star of
a Muslim Turkish general, Mahmud of Ghazna. Indeed, Mallmud became Firdawsis
patron, though it is not surprising in view of his Turkish origin that he and
the poet fell out.° He was soon followed by the Seljuqs, more Muslim Turks.
With Persia largely under Turkish rule Firdawsis conception of the roles of
Iran and Turan had become no more than a political mirage. Persians had become
weaker politically, and in their place Turks were now the military defenders of
Muslim civilization. This was the position from a few years before al-Ghazalis
birth, and it is thus understandable that, though he must have had much Persian
blood in his veins, he never seems to have been attracted by a Persian
solution of current problems or even to have shown special interest in things Persian. 0a
The central figure of this study was born in 1058, four and a half centuries after
the migration of Muhammad from Mecca to Medina, and three years after the
establishment of Seljuq rule in Baghdad. His birth-place was the town or
district of Tus, near the modern Meshed in north-east Persia. His name was
Muhammad, and he was son of Muhammad, son of Muhammad; he had the honorific
title (kunya) of Abu-Hamid, meaning
father of Hamid but not necessarily implying that he had a son of this name
(certainly only daughters survived him). He is best known as al-Ghazali, the
Ghazalite, possibly meaning the man from Ghazala, an otherwise unknown village
in the region of Tus;11 he is sometimes also
called at-Tusi, the Tusite. He had one brother, Ahmad, who became a
distinguished scholar and mystic, and several sisters.
Nothing is known for certain
about his family except that he had a grand-uncle (or less probably uncle),
also called Abu-Hamid al-Ghazali, who was one of the scholars of Tus and died
about 1043. The family was thus in touch with intellectual circles, as is also
shown by the fathers anxiety that his two sons should receive the fullest
possible education. The assertion in some sources that the theologians father
was a spinner and vendor of wool is to be rejected, since it appears to be an
inference from the less probable spelling and derivation of the name Ghazali.
It may be accepted, however, that the father was comparatively poor. On his
death he left as much money as he could with a Sufi friend, charging him to see
that the two boys were well educated. When the money was exhausted the friend
made arrangements for them to go to a college or madrasa where they could receive free board and lodging as well as
instruction. This very brief glimpse of al-Ghazalis family shows that the
family background was not without its influence on his later career. His father
would be characterized by the simple piety of ordinary Muslims, based no doubt
on a considerable knowledge of the Quran and the Traditions which could be
gained by attendance at the lectures given freely in the mosques. Towards the
end of his life al-Ghazali wrote a book in which he advocated prohibiting
ordinary people from attending lectures on theology,1Z but this must be taken
to apply only to the abstruse rational theology of the time and not to the more
concrete forms of religious instruction.
No dates are recorded for the
earlier part of al-Ghazalis education. The normal age to begin schooling was
eleven, and he would be eleven in ro6g.13 In 1077 he went to an
important school or college at Nishapur, the capital of this part of Persia, to
study under the most distinguished theologian of the age, al-Juwayni.4
In the intervening. years he pursued his studies mainly at Tus, apart from a
visit to Gurgan (Jurjan) at the southeast corner of the Caspian Sea. (Nishapur
is about fifty miles from Tus, Gurgan over three hundred, the road passing
through Nishapur; these were comparatively short journeys for a great scholar.),$
The story is told of how the caravan in which the young student was travelling
back from Gurgan was set upon by robbers. Among the goods they seized were the
notebooks, with the harvest of his study in Gurgan. He went after the robbers
and pled for the return of his notebooks, which contained, as he phrased it,
the knowledge he had gained at Gurgan. The robber-chief scoffed at this alleged
knowledge which could be taken away so easily, but gave back the notebooks. The
visit to Gurgan cannot have been later than 1074, since al-Ghazali on his
return spent three years committing his knowledge to memory.
In these years of
study at Tus, Gurgan and Nishapur, al-Ghazali followed the standard curriculum
of Islamic higher education. This had a predominantly legal slant. The basis
was the study of the Quran and Traditions, together with the commentaries on
these. Jurisprudence was derived mainly from the Traditions. Then there were
ancillary sciences such as Arabic grammar, differences between the recognized
legal rites, and biographical knowledge of the transmitters of Traditions. In
al-Ghazalis case, at least until he went to Nishapur, the chief emphasis was
on Traditions and jurisprudence. In these subjects the standard of instruction
in Tits and Gurgan may well have. been high. For over a century
Nishapur and the neighbouring regions had been in the forefront of educational
development, doubtless owing to the virtual independence of the Samanids and
their patronage of learning and the arts,
Instruction in the Islamic
sciences had originally been given in mosques without any fees, and this
practice continued. Gradually, however, special institutions were created. At
first they may have consisted merely of a room or hall and a library. In course
of time livingquarters for the students were added, and funds made available
for their support. To this latter form of institution the name madrasa is given, which may be rendered
college. The first such college seems to have been founded in Nishapur before
960, and this was followed within the century by several others. The movement
of college-founding was vigorously encouraged by Nizam-al-Mulk, the great
Seljuq vizier (in power from 1063 to 1092). One source suggests that he was the
first to provide scholarships for the students; but some earlier cases are
known.16 What is certain is that he founded at least nine Nizamiyya
colleges, scattered from Mosul to Herat, and that they were lavishly endowed.
In 1077 Nishapur had enjoyed relative peace under the Seljuqs for nearly forty
years, whereas Baghdad had been the scene of strife, which must have made
academic work difficult, till after
the Seljuq occupation in log g. It might, therefore, be expected that the level
of academic attainment in the region of Nishapur would be among the highest in
the Islamic world.
In particular, when al-Ghazali
went to Nishapur in 1077 it was to the Nizamiyya college he went, attracted by
the fame of the great theologian, Abu-1-Ma`ali aluwayni, known as
Imam-al-Haramayn, the imam of the two holy places (Mecca and Medina).
Al-Juwayni was the son of a professor or lecturer at Nishapur, but was admitted
by all to be more brilliant than his father. He was primarily a theologian, and
introduced al-Ghazali to theology, perhaps the most difficult of the Islamic
sciences. Al-Ghazali remained at Nishapur until al-Juwaynis death in August
108$, and latterly helped with teaching. Then he went to the camp of
Nizam-al-Mulk, and was received by the vizier with honour and respect, though
still only twenty-seven. Though one would have expected him to go on teaching
in Nishapur, the records suggest that he spent the whole of the next few years
at the camp, until his appointment as professor at the Nizamiyya college in
Baghdad in July 1091.17
Thus we see that al-Ghazali had
an education as good as any to be had in the Islamic world. Al-Juwayni was the
first theologian of his time. His teachers in Tradition were not so eminent,
but his inexactitude in quoting Traditions and his use of uncanonical
Traditions are probably due mainly to his own slackness and unorthodoxy.
Education, too, had struck deep roots in the region round Nishapur and Tus, and
had influenced many classes of society. This meant that al-Ghazali, while
gaining an excellent education, was not cut off from the simple but
well-informed faith of the ordinary people. Al-Ju-wayni is reported to have
made a statement which indicates how the younger man was moulded by the older
in this point and in others:, 8
I heard Abu-1-Ma`ali al-Juwayni saying, I had read
thousands of books; then I left the people of Islam with their religion and
their manifest sciences in these books, and I embarked on the open sea,
plunging into the literature the people of Islam rejected. All this was in
quest of truth. At an early age I fled from the acceptance of others opinions (taqlid). But now l have
returned from everything to the word of the Truth, `Hold to the religion of the
old women. If the Truth does not grasp me by the grace of His justice, so that
I die in the religion of the old women and the result of my life is sealed at
my departure with the purity of the people of Truth and the word of sincerity,
`There is no god but God, then alas for the son of al-Juwayni (that is,
himself).
THE ENCOUNTER WITH PHILOSOPHY
I THE PHILOSOPHICAL
MOVEMENT IN
THE ISLAMIC WORLD
IN its main outlines the story is well known of how Greek
philosophy entered the Islamic world and was partly incorporated into Islamic
theology, but about the details there is still
much obscurity., The aim of this and the following section is not to investigate some of the many
remaining obscurities, but to look at the place of the philosophers in Islamic
society.
It was only under the
earlyAbbasids that Muslims began to have effective contacts with Greek
learning, though within the territories ruled by the caliph this was still
alive at a number of Christian colleges, notably one at Gunde-Shaper (or
Junday-saber, about a hundred miles north-east of Basra). The decisive step was
taken by the caliph al-Mansur (regnabat
754-775), whose health was not good, when in 765 he summoned to
his court a doctor from Gunde-Shaper, George of the Persian-Nestorian family of
Bokhtishu`; until 87o the post of court
physician was held by George and his descendants, and other members of the
family are heard of subsequently.2 From 765 onwards interest in all the aspects
of Greek learning grew in the court circle, encouraged by such men as the
Barmakid family of viziers. Noted patrons and amateurs of Greek learning were
Harnn ar-Rashid (regnabat 786-8o9)
and his son alMamun (813-833). Under the three caliphs mentioned and their
immediate successors a beginning was made with the work of translating
Greek books into Arabic (usually from the Syriac translations already possessed
by the Christian colleges), and a few bold spirits would attempt to combine
Greek and Islamic ideas.
Three
main stages may be distinguished in the work of translation. The first is that
already described. To begin with, the patronage was sporadic, but al-Mamiin
gave the matter an institutional basis by setting up a
house of wisdom (bays d-hikma), which
was both a
library and a centre for the
copying and translating of books. By 85o a fair number of Greek medical texts
and several of the
works of Aristotle and other philosophers were available in Arabic. Since an
Arabic technical vocabulary in these disciplines had to be created, the
achievement was considerable, even if some of the more abstruse works were
still imperfectly comprehended. The second stage is that of Hunayn ibn-Ishaq (vivebat 808-873) and his son and other
pupils. Hunayn was of Arab descent, had studied grammar at Basra and medicine
at Baghdad, and then travelled widely in the Byzantine empire as well as the
Islamic. From his travels he brought back an excellent knowledge of Greek and a
valuable collection of manuscripts. His scholarly standards in translation were
of the highest; for him a necessary preliminary of translations was the
construction of a critical Greek text. In general the translations of Hunayn
and his school reached a new level of accuracy and comprehension. The third
stage in the work of translation corresponds roughly to the tenth century.
Owing to the development of original philosophical writing in Arabic there was
a more profound undrrrstanding of the problems and a richer technical
vocabulary. Some of the older translations were revised (as Hunayn also had
done). Such fresh translations as were made, however, were from Syriac and not
directly from Greek.
It was
mainly out of the work of translation that the independent philosophical
movement grew in the Islamic world. In this movement there are various trends.
With the attachment to the caliphal court of the family of Bokhtishi, the
medical tradition of Gunde-Shapur began to take root in Baghdad. There was a
hospital under the supervision of the court physician, and here medical
teaching was given. There was probably also some instruction in philosophy;
certainly all doctors of the period studied philosophy.
A
second important strand was the philosophical tradition of Alexandria. The
great college at Alexandria had never had very close relations with its
Copticspeaking Egyptian hinterland, being essentially a Greek institution. It
is significant that Syriac had begun to replace Greek before the Arab conquest.
This latter event presumably led to the withdrawal of the remaining
Greek-speaking (as distinct from Syriac-speaking or Coptic-speaking) teachers.
The connection with Syriac scholarship doubtless determined the selection of
Antioch as a new site for the college about 718, when it had presumably become
too small to continue in Egypt. Round about 85o there was another move, this
time westwards to Harran (about halfway along the route to Mosul), and towards
goo yet another, to Baghdad. These moves were essentially moves of the
teachers, the living bearers of the philosophical tradition, though on some
occasions they are also reported as having taken the library with them. From
about 850 something is known about the chief philosophers connected with this
tradition. In particular there was a lively philosophical coterie meeting in
the house of Abu-Sulayman al-Mantigi as-Sijistani in Baghdad in the last
quarter of the tenth century.3
There were also other strands about which we are not so well
informed. The so-called sect of Sibians in Harran had made some study of Greek
philosophy, and certain members of it became involved in the translation work
and the philosophical movement in Baghdad. The college transferred from Antioch
to Harran, however, seems to have been separate and under Christian direction.
In the eastern parts of the caliphate there were also some philosophical
studies, which made possible the appearance of a man like Muhammad ibn-Zakariya
arRazi. It seems likely that philosophical works were translated into Persian
at Gunde-Shaper and elsewhere, but the suggestion that works of Aristotle were
translated from Persian into Arabic has been shown to be without foundation.¢
What of
the people who were involved in this philosophical movement? Who were they,
what was their position in society, and why were they interested in philosophy?
First
of all there were the caliphs like al-Mansur and al-Mamun. As they became
aware of the foreign sciences which were being cultivated within their
empire, they must have wanted to gain what practical benefits were to be had
from them. Medical treatment had obvious advantages, and so doctors are found
to have played a large part in the philosophical movement. Astrology was also
assigned a high practical importance, and the contemporary amalgam of astrology
and astronomy was much cultivated. Mathematics, too, had its practical use. The
same could not be said of philosophy, but it may have been included because it
was closely linked with the other branches of Greek learning. In any case it
was a part of this new, exciting and in some ways higher culture.
Al-Mamun
had as friends and advisers a group of Islamic theologians known as Mtf
tazilites. Some of these had been involved in defending Islam by argument
against non-Muslims, and they soon perceived the usefulness of Greek logic and
other Greek philosophical ideas in such arguments. Consequently they boldly
engaged in speculation, and interpreted traditional Islamic doctrines in terms
of Greek ideas to the scandal of the more conservative theologians. They will
have to be discussed more fully at a later stage of this study. Here, after
this brief mention, they may be left aside, since they were not philosophers
but theologians who to a limited extent made use of Greek ideas.
At a later period than that of al-Mamun, minor rulers in the
provinces are found patronizing students of philosophy and the other Greek
sciences. In some cases they may have been chiefly interested in a mans
medical knowledge; but al-Farabi, who never practised as a doctor, was
well-received at the court of Sayf-ad-Dawla in Syria (about 945). In such a
case it may be that the local ruler was emulating the court of the caliph; but
it is also conceivable that he may have wanted to maintain a degree of
independence from the scholar-jurists (though this is a point which requires
further investigation).
Of the
many Christians involved in the philosophical movement nothing will be said
here, since their motives can only be understood in the context of the history
of the relations between Christianity and philosophy. Some of the Christians
gained a living as doctors, others had positions in their ecclesiastical
institutions.
The
point on which our attention must be focussed is the chain of Muslim
philosophers and the position of each in society.
(1) The earliest of
all, al-Kind-15 (c. Boo-866 or-873), known as the philosopher of
the Arabs, came from an Arab family which had held official posts rising to
the governorship of Ku£a. He himself was attached to the caliphal court, and
was tutor to a son of one of the caliphs. He had a large library, presumably
mainly ofbooks in the Greek sciences, in which he was an expert. The library
was removed to Basra to inconvenience him as the result of a court intrigue,
but was subsequently restored.
(2) A pupil of
al-Kindis, Ahmad ibn-at-Tayyib as-Sarakhsi (d. 896), had administrative and
other positions at the caliphs court, including the tutorship of a future
caliph, but had time to write about philosophy.6
(3) After the
transference of the former Alexandrian college from Harran to Baghdad a man
called Ibn-Karnib is said to have become head of it (shortly after goo?). His
father and brother were mathematicians and wrote on astronomy, and he himself
is said to have been both a theologian (mutakallim)
and a natural-scientist. He earned his living, however, as a secretary (or
civil servant).
(4) The great
physician ar-Razi, known in Europe as Rhazes (865-923 or -932), completed his
education at Baghdad, though he spent the early part of his life at Rayy (near
modern Teheran). He worked as a physician at a hospital in Baghdad and at the
courts of several pro vincial rulers.
(5) Al-Farabi (873-950),
the second Teacher (Aristotle being the first), was born in Turkestan,
but eventually came to Baghdad and studied philosophy and other Greek sciences.
How he supported himself is not clear, but he lived an ascetic life and may
have needed little. In his closing years he was at the court of Sayf-ad-Dawla
of Aleppo (regnabat 944-967),
occupied in writing books and teacbing.7
(6) Close to the
philosophical circle stood the widelytravelled bookseller Ibn-an-Nadim (d. c.
996), whose Fihrist or Catalogue (of allexistingArabic books
known to him, with biographical notes on the authors) is a mine of information
about many subjects, including the philosophical movement here described.
(7) A minor figure
was Isa (d. tool), son of the good vizier Ali ibnIsa. He was a secretary to the caliphs, and
one of the few men in the
philosophical circles of whom we know definitely that he had made some study of
the Islamic
sciences, in particular of Tradition.
(8) From at least about 98o there
flourished in Baghdad a most varied philosophical circle, meeting in the house
of Abu-Sulayman as-Sijistani, the logician (d. after root). Students from
many different backgrounds interested in one or other of the Greek sciences met
and discussed topics of literary, scientific or philosophical interest. Though
Abu-Sulayman stood well in the eyes of the Buwayhid prince Adud-ad-Dawla (regnabat in Baghdad 977-983), he
appears to have held no official post but to have lived in retirement, apart
from the meetings in his house.
(9) Some of these discussions
have been described by the hosts younger friend, AbuHayyan at-Tawhidi (d.
after 1010). This man was a Persian with Mu`tazilite leanings, and a man of
letters rather than a philosopher; he also knew something of Islamic law. By
profession he was a scribe and amanuensis, latterly serving as secretary to
viziers and other court officials in Baghdad and the provinces.
(10)
Ibn-Khammar (d. 1017), a Christian who became a Muslim, was a physician and
philosopher who latterly was at the courts of Khwarizm and Ghazna in the east. (11) Another man who was not exactly a
philosopher was the Persian Miskawayh (d. 1030), who was secretary
and librarian to several viziers. (12) A man with considerable philosophical
talent was the Sahib, Ibn--`Abbad (d.
995), the son of a secretary in Rayy, who rose to be vizier there and made
himself semi-independent. (13) Ibn-Hindu (d. after 1018), another Persian,
though perhaps of Indian extraction, was a secretary of Persian princes.
(14) The great Ibn-Sins or Avicenna (980-1037), probably another
Persian, was the son of a minor administrator in Transoxiana under the Samanid
dynasty. His first interest in philosophy came from a Fatimid propagandist,
though he also had some traditional Islamic instruction. An otherwise unknown
teacher introduced him to the works of the Greek philosophers and scientists,
and he continued to read them by himself until he had fully mastered their contents.
The chance purchase of a book by al-Farabi gave him fresh insight, which
completed his philosophical development. He worked as a high minister of state
at various courts in the unsettled times of the early eleventh century.8 (I5) Shortly after these men
a self-taught physician and philosopher appears in Cairo, Ibn-Bidwan (d. 1061).9 (16)
Abul-Hasan Said Hibatallah (d. 1102) was physician in charge of a
hospital in Baghdad and also a philosopher. (17) Ibn-Jazla (d. 1100), a pupil
of the last-named, was originally a Christian, but was persuaded by his
Mu`tazilite instructor in logic, Abu-`Ali ibn-al-Walid, to become a Muslim. He
subsequently obtained an official post at the law-courts.
What
stands out clearly from this list is that the bearers of the Greek sciences and
the new Islamic philosophy were quite different from the bearers of Islamic
religious learning.
Only in
one or two cases are men with a competence in philosophy reported to have made
any advanced study of Traditions or the SharVa; and it may be that even these
few had not progressed far. Moreover, those who pursued philosophical studies,
unless they were doctors or found a patron at some court, were unable to gain a
living from their studies but had to work as secretaries or in humbler ways.
For philosophy to flourish as it did there must have been many enthusiasts
among them.
The
close link between the philosophical movement and the class of secretaries or
civil servants suggests the question whether there is any connection between
this attraction of philosophy for them in the tenth and eleventh centuries and
the interest they showed in Manichaeanism in the eighth century. Then it seems
probable that the class of secretaries, conscious that from Sasanian times they
had been the bearers of PersoIraqian culture, saw in Manichaeanism a basis from
which to criticize the growing class of Islamic scholarjurists, which was
threatening to become a dangerous rival.° In the tenth and eleventh centuries
this rivalry still existed, and philosophy also might provide a basis for
criticism; but the next section will show that there is little that can be
called an attack on the scholar-jurists, only attempts at self-justification
with a view to selfpreservation. If there is anything in the suggestion above that
the rulers interested in philosophy were anxious to reduce their dependence on
the scholar-jurists, their support of the secretary-philosophers would coalesce
with the latters effort to remain independent. What has been said in this
paragraph is all somewhat conjectural, but it does not affect the fact of the link between the secretaries and the
philosophical movement.
The
essence of the situation was that there were two separate educational systems
in the Islamic empire, the old Greek one and the new Islamic one. It was not
unlike the situation in most Islamic countries during the past century, when
there was the traditional Islamic educational system with its crown in
universities like al-Azhar in Cairo and a modern system culminating in
Western-style universities. The parallel must not be pressed too far, however.
There was much less organization in medieval times, and in particular the study
of Greek science and philosophy was hardly organized at all except at the
teaching hospitals, and it is doubtful whether we are justified in speaking of
a philosophical school or college at Baghdad except in the sense that there was
a group of like-minded people. There was certainly such a group, however, and
there was certainly continuity in their thought. Before trying to say any more
about them we must consider some of the things they themselves said.
2 THE SOCIAL RELEVANCE OF
PHILOSOPHICAL IDEAS
One of the basic conceptions of this study is that, whether men are
aware of it or not, their ideas reflect social facts and social aspirations.
Plato had an understanding of our problem, and in the Republic gives prominence to the parallelism between an
individuals powers and the class-structure of society. The ideal state for him
was one where the intellectuals were the ruling class, and in accordance with
this view he engaged in politics to the extent of trying to make the ruler of a
small state a philosopher-prince. Yet he was also aware of the difficulty of
realizing this ideal in practice. There is another strand in his thought which
distinguishes between the unchanging world of the forms and the ordinary world
of becoming and dissolution, genesis and
phthora. According to this strand of
his thought the proper work of the intellect or reasonand so, we infer, of the
intellectual-is not in controlling the mutable things of space and time, but in
dealing with the immutable forms; in other words, the intellectuals contract
out of politics, and leave public affairs to those who have the knack. The
allegory of the cave in the Republic attempts
to explain why the philosophers, who know the realities of which the shadows
are seen in the cave, are often worse at dealing with the shadows than those
who have not philosophized. These strands were still present in the Greek philosophical
tradition when, more than a millennium after Plato, it thrust itself upon the
Muslims; and the position of philosophers in Hellenistic and Byzantine society
was a
factor,
even if a minor one, in determining the place of philosophers in Islamic society.
(a) _4r-Raga
In surveying the social
implications of Islamic philosophical thought it is convenient to begin with
ar-Razi (d. 923 or 932), though he was younger than al-Kindi. He
stands somewhat apart from the other great philosophers of Islam, being less
under the influence of Proclus than they.
Ar-Razi accepts the Platonic
conception of the soul as tripartite,1? which implies the superiority of
reason; and he has much to say about the control of the passions by reason.
Reason is also the source of all civilized life:
God gave us reason, chiefly that we might attain the
utmost benefits we are capable of, both temporal and eternal. It is the
greatest of Gods gifts; nothing is more profitable for us. By Reason we are
superior to the brute beasts; we subjugate them, and employ them in ways useful
both to us and them. By Reason we apprehend all that elevates us, and
beautifies and enriches our life; by it we attain our hearts desire. By Reason
we learn how to build and sail ships, and thereby reach lands beyond the seas.
By it we acquire the medical art, to the great advantage of our bodies, and the
other useful arts. By it we apprehend what is obscure, far-off and concealed.
By it we know the shape of earth and
sky, and the magnitude, distance and motions of sun, moon and stars. By it we
come to knowledge of the Creator, the summit of our comprehension and chief
source of our welfare. In short, without Reason our condition would be that of
beasts, children and madmen.13
Despite this realization of the
contribution of Reason to the fabric of the life of the community, ar-Razi
shows
34
35
F
MUSLIM INTELLECTUAL
no desire that reason should
guide and control political affairs. He advises people not to try to raise
their status by engaging in politics. He defends himself against the charge of
having consorted with princes, by pointing out that he has held no appointment
in the army or civil service, but has merely treated the princes body when he
was ill, and given him counsel in health. He has not aimed at increasing his
wealth, but has been content with a modest sufficiency; and we know that he
must have worked incessantly at his medical and other scientific studies and in
writing his numerous books. His ideal is what he calls the philosophic life,
a life of intellectual activity. The rational part of the soul falls short of
its true nature unless it sees the wonder and grandeur of the world, meditates
on it and marvels at it, and has an insatiable desire for knowledge of all that
is in it, especially the science of the body in which it finds itself and its
shape and condition after death 14
The most positive things he has
to say about political life are in a little essay entitled The Signs of WorldlyAdvancement
and Political Power. The theme of this is that certain people are
marked out to be rulers of men. Nature has endowed them with qualities of
character such as nobility and perhaps a certain personal magnetism which make
others follow them and accept them as leaders. That such people should actually
rule he regards as right and proper. In this he seems to be inclining to
fatalism, for there is something ineluctable about these differences fixed by
nature. This is not altogether consistent with his general view of reason. At
other times, however, he maintains that all men are equally endowed with
reason, and on this ground argues against the conception of God sending
prophets, since these give knowledge to some people and not to others. This is
implicitly an attack on the existing Islamic basis of society.
THE ENCOUNTER WITH PHILOSOPHY
In general, ar-Razis version of
Platonism becomes a justification for the kind of life he was leading, a life
of intellectual, mainly scientific, pursuits apart from the main stream of
society. His philosophy enabled him to think and feel that he was doing
something significant. He was allowing the highest or rational part of him to
live its proper life. To put it in another way, the aim of human life is to
become as like God as possible; God is all-knowing, all-just and all-merciful;
and so man must endeavour to grow in knowledge, justice and mercy.$ Knowledge,
we observe, comes first. From our vantagepoint of over ten centuries later we
can see that ar-Razi was indeed playing a most important part in the life of Islamic
society, but his theory did not account for all he was in fact achieving, nor
was he himself aware of its full importance.
(b) Al-Kindi
The most distinctive and most
important line in Islamic philosophy-to be roughly described as Neoplatonism on
a basis of Aristotelian logic-begins with al-Kindi (d. 866) and leads on to
al-Farabi and Avicenna. Al-Kindis thought has many similarities with that of
ar-Razi. He considers it one of the functions of reason, or rather of the soul,
to control the passions; and he emphasizes the distinction between the
transient things which are the objects of the passions or sensuous desires, and
the lasting good which is the object of rational desire. On the other hand, his
conception of the soul (nafs) is more
developed and more Aristotelian than that of ar-Razi. Among the points he makes
in his Essay on the Soul are that it
restrains anger and desire, that it persists after death, that when it is
purified it has true knowledge of things, and that its true habitation
is in
the higher supernal world (`alam
ar-rububiyya).16 This is
still not unlike ar-Razi; but his Essay
on the
36
37
MUSLIM INTELLECTUAL
Reason is explicitly Aristotelian and leads on to alFarabis fuller
work with the same title.? The conception of emanation (faya) frequently occurs; and God is spoken of as the only true
agent, the only one who acts upon others but is not himself acted upon. 8
The relation of these ideas to
their social context is not obvious so long as we look only at al-Kind-1,
but it becomes apparent when we notice how al-Farabi treated them. What is
remarkable in al-Kindi is the absence of any sense of conflict or tension
between philosophy and the Islamic sciences. Unlike ar-Razi, who criticized the
conception of prophethood, al-Kindi always speaks as a good Muslim. He asserts
that the knowledge brought by truthful prophets is identical with the results
of first philosophy or metaphysics; and he interprets the Quran in terms of
the Greek scientific world-view.19 On the practical side, he holds that the
soul which has been illuminated is entrusted by God with the conduct of
political affairs.Zo In all this al-Kindi probably reflects the political
situation from about 8zo to 85o, when many of the highest posts were held by
men of Me tazilite views and when the caliphs also had leanings in this
direction. The Mu tazilites were Islamic theologians with a moderate knowledge
of Greek philosophy. Thus the caliphate was in fact being administered by a
group of intellectuals of whom al-Kind-1 could approve. He himself
was much more fully acquainted with Greek learning and less interested in
theology and less involved in politics. This seems to explain why his works
show no awareness of the underlying tensions between philosophers and
scholar-jurists.
(c) A1-Fdrdhi
The political
implications in the Islamic world of the Neoplatonic conception of emanation
become clear in the thought of al-Farabi (d. 95o), who has left several
THE ENCOUNTER WITH
PHILOSOPHY
works on politics. According to
this concept the universe is hierarchical in the sense that at its summit is
the most perfect being, the being that most truly is, and that from this being
proceed less perfect beings and from these a lower grade of being until the
lowest of all is reached. In the same way al-Farabi regards the city or
civilized community as hierarchical. At the summit is the head or leader (rais). Then come the leaders of second
rank, then those of the third, until the lowest rank is reached consisting of
those who follow others but do not themselves lead any others. The supreme
leader is he who leads or commands or controls others, but is not himself led
or commanded or controlled by others.
There are various points to be
noticed about this conception of the state. Firstly, the qualities which mark
out the leader are not purely rational or intellectual. AlFarabi has a long
list of the qualities required by the supreme leader, and they include moral
excellences and gifts of personality. One is reminded of ar-Razis view that
some men are naturally marked out to be leaders. By thus widening the
conception of reason al-Farabi brings his theory close to the political facts
of his time, though, as we shall see, he regards his conception of the state as
an ideal seldom to be realized. Secondly, alFarabis account of the state is
not far removed from the old ideas of autocratic sovereignty associated with
the east. The supreme leader is the source of the whole life of the state. This
fits exactly some of the early conceptions of the divine kingship in the Middle
Fast 21 It also fits the
contemporary practice.
The grades of the people of the
city in leadership or service are higher or lower according to their natural
disposition and upbringing. The first leader grades the group; and every man in
every group is in the grade of which he is worthy, either of service or of
leadership.
... The leader, after assigning these
grades, when he wants something different, can make fresh ordinances.... zZ
This activity of the first leader is exactly that of the
caliph. In the `Abbasid state (as contrasted with the Umayyad) inherited
nobility counted for little, whether it was that of the pre-Islamic Arab
aristocracy or that of the Islamic families ennobled by the stipend system and
similar measures. TheAbbasid court consisted of men who had been given
positions by the caliph for their own merits and usefulness (even if some were
also sons of courtiers), and they could be removed from their positions just as
easily as they could be placed in them. They were the caliphs creations.
In all this al-Farabis views are
close to those of the Shiites, who also emphasize the leader. Yet there is a
difference, for the leader sought by the Shiites was one with charismata which
were independent of any personal effort of his and which placed him in a
category above ordinary men. It is possible to take al-FArabis views in a
Shiite sense, but it is not necessary to do so, and therefore it would be wrong
to infer from his conception of the state that be had Shiite leanings.23
The idea, then, of the emanation
of all being from the supreme Being, apart from its attractiveness as a
harmonious world-view embracing all the science of the day, appealed to the
deep-seated tradition of autocratic rule and the ordinary (educated) mans sense
of being dependent on some one above him. Al-Farabi, however, modifies strict
logic to make his thought accord better with the historical situation of his
day. The supreme leader is described as a prophet-philosopher.24
When that occurs (the inherence of the active reason in a man) in both parts of his rational faculty, speculative and practical, and then in his imaginative faculty, that man is the one to whom revelation is given, and it is God who reveals to him by means of the active reason; what flows (or emanates) from God to the active reason, the active reason pours into his passive reason by means of the acquired reason, and then into his imaginative faculty. By what is poured into his passive reason he becomes wise, a philosopher, altogether prudent; by what is poured into his imaginative faculty, he becomes a prophet, warning about what will be, and announcing the particulars which now are.... Such a man is in the most perfect grade of humanity, and in the highest degree of happiness....
One difficulty
caused by thus making the supreme leader a prophet is that, according to the
standard Sunnite view, there has been no prophet in the Islamic state since
Muhammad. Al-Farabi has therefore to justify the following of Muhammads
example although he has been long dead. After the above description of the
first leader or prophet-philosopher and a list of thirteen qualities he ought
to have, there comes an account of the second leader who follows the
first.25 This is not a second-in-command but a successor. The Arabic word
translated follow, yakhlufu, has
the connotation of following as a deputy, vicegerent or replacement, that is,
as a caliph, khalifa. This successor
has to have six qualities. He must be wise (that is, a philosopher); he must know
and remember and follow the revealedlaws, customs and manner of life (sharui`, sunan, siyar) established for
the state by the first ones; he must be good at deducing new applications for
their principles; he must be good at devising experimental ways of dealing with
entirely new situations; he must be good at persuading people to accept his
policies; he must be able to endure the hardships of war. AI-Farabi then
continues:
If there is no one man in whom
all these conditions are fulfilled but if there are two, one with wisdom
(philosophy), and the other with the remaining qualities, then these two should
be leaders in this city. If the qualities are distributed among a group, so
that one has wisdom, another the second quality, another the third, and so on,
and if the men are mutually suitable, they should be the superior leaders. When
it happens at some time that wisdom (philosophy) is not a part of the
leadership .. . the virtuous city remains without a king....
This is an attempt to bring the
description of the ideal state within measurable distance of the actual state.
One important point to notice is that in all these discussions there is
complete acceptance of the Islamic basis of the state. The supreme leader has
to be portrayed with the features of the prophet Muhammad. Even for a
philosopher like al-Farabi there is no conceivable alternative to the existing
Islamic state. What he does try to
maintain is that the philosophers should have a say in the running of the state
comparable to that of the scholarjurists. The second and third qualities of the
second leader seem to be meant to be those of the Traditionists and
scholar-jurists; and the suggestion is that, when the qualities are divided
out, the bearers of each quality are approximately equal. In so far as
philosophers had a position at court (or in the civil service) and were able to influence the ruler (central or
provincial) by their advice, there was some truth in this claim for the
philosophers; but on the whole their influence must have been decreasing and
that of the scholar-jurists increasing.
While this conclusion is to be
drawn from the passage quoted above, another passage shows that al-Farabi
regarded the work of the philosopher as more fundamental than that of the scholar-jurist.z6 Knowledge is required
by the citizens of the virtuous state, but this may be of two kinds, either
conceiving, rational conception, or imaging, imaginative understanding.
Most men are unable to have a rational conception of what as citizens they need
to know, such as the ultimate principles of existing things and their
hierarchical order, the nature of happiness and of supreme leadership in the
state, and the particular acts conducive to happiness. For such men the higher
powers produce symbols and images by means of the prophets, and these symbols
and images may vary from people to people and religion to religion, some being
better than others, but the things themselves are the same for all. Here
al-Farabi is trying to exalt the philosopher, who handles absolute truth, above
the scholar-jurist, whose material has only relative truth. Is this perhaps
because he realizes that the scholar-jurists have more actual influence than
the philosophers?
Altogether al-Farabi is a
fascinating author on the subject of politics. He fully accepts the Islamic
state, but interprets it in Neoplatonic terms. He tries hard to make a place in
his scheme for the scholar-jurists, and in some passages succeeds; but at other
times he is unable to conceal his essential belief that the real successors of
the Platonic intellectuals are the philosophers in the Greek tradition.
(d) Avicenna
The physician and philosopher Avicenna or IbnSina (d.
1037) worked out a philosophical system on similar lines to al-Farabl, to whose
books he acknowledged his indebtedness. He is generally reckoned the more
profound philosopher of the two. Among the similarities which specially concern
the present study are the full acceptance of the Islamic state system and the
framing of a theory of prophecy in terms of Neoplatonic epistemology. Since his
epistemology differs slightly from that of his predecessor, it is only natural
that there are some small differences in the theory of prophecy. He also takes
the view that for ordinary people, who are mostly incapable of philosophic
thinking, religion must be expressed in symbolic form.
He differs from al-Farabi,
however, in various ways. In general he has far less to say about politics. He
apparently never discusses the question of second leaders, but instead
regards it as part of the office of the prophet to make provision for the
maintenance of his religious and social system after his death. On the whole,
the position of the prophet is enhanced. Prophets are a rare phenomenon.
Prophetic apprehension of truth, though it may come about instantaneously, is
not authority-based (taglidi) but
rational (`agli).27 The work of the prophet, too, is more fundamental than that
of the philosopher, since it is absolutely essential for the welfare of the
state. Only the formulations of the prophet give ordinary people the knowledge
requisite if the state is to prosper. In so far as the philosophers
formulations are comprehensible only to the few, the philosophers would seem to
be less useful.2$
The differences between Avicenna
and al-Farabi may be linked up with certain differences in their historical
situations. Al-Farabi had died in 9Io, whereas Avicennas life stretched from
980 to 1037. In 969 the Fatimids from Tunisia had conquered Egypt, and soon
afterwards founded Cairo to be their capital. They claimed to be the rightful
caliphs or leaders of the whole community of Muslims, and without delay began
to send out emissaries eastwards to work for the overthrow of theAbbasid
caliphate by the dissemination of Fatimid-Ismailite propaganda. This
propaganda doubtless also threatened the autonomous states subordinate to the
caliphate. Even the Shiites in theAbbasid domains (including the Buwayhid
sultans in Baghdad) would be threatened, since practically none of them accepted
the
Ismailite form of Shi ism. Now much of al-Farabis
political philosophy, even if he himself was not a Shiite, was capable of being
used to justify Shiite and indeed Fatimid policies. He tended to place the
emphasis on the actual leader or ruler of the state in the present. Avicenna,
on the other hand, says nothing about the flow of divine wisdom into and
through the actual ruler. His emphasis is on the founding of the Islamic
religion and community by Muhammad nearly four centuries earlier. This is much
more of a Sunnite position, and not unlike that adopted by al-Ghazali towards
the Ismailites.
Another fact to be remembered
about Avicenna is that he had a prominent place at various minor courts in the
east of the caliphate, such as Bukhara, Gurganj, Hamadhan and Ispahan,
sometimes even being vizier or chief minister. Thus he had as much political
power as he wanted, and sometimes refused appointments. His relation to the
governments under which he served is not unlike that of the Mutazilites of Baghdad
in the period round about the caliphate of al-Mamun (813-. 833). It is
therefore significant that bothheand the Mif tazilites should think that their
interpretation of Islam in terms of Greek thought was a genuine account of
traditional Islam. (Avicennas account, of course, was much more philosophical
than that of the Mu tazilites.) In so far as they, philosophically minded men,
had more political influence than the scholar-jurists, they were able to
present their philosophical interpretation of Islam as the standard
interpretation. There was no need to exaggerate the importance of philosophy
because there was no need to seek greater political influence for
philosophically-minded men.
Avicenna was also attracted to
mysticism. What is the explanation of this? Can it in any way be regarded as a
reaction to political impotence? He was not altogether impotent, but he lived
in a very disturbed period and may well have felt that any good work a man
might do was liable to be swept away by a sudden change in the current of
fortune. In his Autobiography he
tells how he had just managed to reach a point from which he could have
approached Qabus, the ruler of Gurgan
and Tabaristan, when the latter was taken prisoner and died; he would doubtless
have proved an enlightened patron. Avicenna must also have felt that little of
lasting importance could be achieved by political action. He has therefore no
romantic hopes of a reform of the existing state system by statesmen, however
philosophical. Instead he turns to the cultivation of the inner life. He
sometimes speaks about three stages, those of the ascetic, the worshipper and
the gnostic (Iahid, `dbid, `drif ), and
describes the last stage in detail.29 This was clearly an important part of his
own experience. It may have been in part an expression of his despair of
historical achievement, butmuch more it seems to spring from a realization that
the significance of life is to be found beyond history.
(e) Abu-Sulayman al Mantiqi
as-Sajistani
A contrary reaction to that of
Avicenna is possibly shown by Abu-Sulayman of Sijistan (d. 1001), known as the
logician. The explanation may lie in the fact that he and most of the coterie
which met in his house were comparatively uninfluential politically. An account
has been preserved of a meeting after the death of the Buwayhid sultan
`Adud-ad-Dawla in 983, when they emulated the ten philosophers who made
epigrams on the death of Alexander.30 Abu-Sulayman opened with a severe
criticism of the deceased ruler: This person weighed the world in an improper
scale, and assigned it an undue price. It is enough that seeking profit in the
world he lost his soul. After the others had spoken he quoted from the
official Friday sermon when the death was announced: What hast thou accomplished
with thy goods and slaves and retainers and army, with thy stored wealth and
keen wit? Why didst thou not make a friend of Him who set thee on the throne,
and bestow all on Him? .. . He knew thy weakness who designed thy fall, and
they little knew thee who thought thee mighty! Nay, He made thee king who
ruined thee with sovereignty, and He dethroned thee who designed thy doom!
Truly thou art a warning to all that will be warned, and a sign to all that
have eyes to see!
Now `Adud-ad-Dawla is generally
reckoned a strong and successful ruler by modern historians, though he was not
able to prevent his family from quarrelling after his death about the
succession; and the bitterness of the criticism is surprising. It is
reminiscent of some earlier criticisms of the caliphs by scholar-jurists. What
seems most likely is that Abu-Sulayman and his friends, feeling that their
merits were not given sufficient public recognition, were withdrawing into
themselves, and at the same time asserting the superiority of their
philosophical way of life.
After this examination of the progress of philosophy in
the Islamic world, it is possible to appreciate better al-Ghazalis description
of the period of scepticism through which he passed. It is convenient to begin
with an abbreviated version of what he says in his autobiographical work Deliverance from Error.3 He begins
by saying to a brother in religion that he will try to tell him what he has
found in his quest for truth, and explains how from his earliest youth he tried
to have a genuine understanding of the various sects and religious movements
with which he came in contact, and how he was puzzled by the fact that men
appear to become Jews or Christians or Muslims because of environmental
influences. He wondered how the beliefs acquired from parents and teachers
could be tested for their truth, and whether there was a natural religion prior
to these environmental influences.
I said to myself, I am seeking knowledge of what things
really are, so I must know what knowledge is. I saw that certain knowledge must
exclude all doubt and the possibility of error, indeed even the supposition of
this. The person who performs miracles should not be able to shake ones
conviction of the truth of such knowledge. For example, if someone says, `Three
is greater than ten, and the proof is that I shall turn this rod into a
serpent, and if he actually does it in my presence, I still do not doubt my
knowledge, but only wonder how he achieved the transformation. From such
considerations I realized that only where I have an unshakable conviction of
this kind is my knowledge certain knowledge.
When I examined my
knowledge, I found that none of it was certain except matters of
sense-perception and necessary truths. It further occurred to me, however, that
my present trust in sense-perception and necessary truths was perhaps no better
founded than my previous trust in propositions accepted from parents and
teachers. So I earnestly set about making myself doubt sense perception and
necessary truths. With regard to sense perception I noticed that the sense of
sight tells me that the shadow cast by the gnomon of a sundial is motionless;
but later observation and reflection shows that it moves, and that it does so not
by jerks but by a constant steady motion. This sense also tells me that the sun
is the size of a coin but astronomical proofs show that it is larger than the
earth. Thus sense makes certain judgements, and then reason comes and judges
that they are false.
I said to myself, `Since my
trust in sense-perception has proved vain, perhaps all that is to be relied on
are rational propositions and first principles, such as that ten is more than
three, that negation and affirmation cannot both hold of anything, that a thing
cannot be both originated-in-time and eternal, both existent and non-existent,
necessary and impossible. Then sense perception said, `Do you not expect that
your trust in rational propositions will fare like your trust in sense
perception? You used to trust in me, but judge Reason came and showed I was
false. Perhaps beyond rational apprehension there will be another judge; when
he appears he will show that reason is false. The fact that this supra-rational
apprehension has not appeared yet, does not show that it is impossible.
While my self was
hesitating about the reply to this, sense-perception increased its difficulties
by a reference to dreams, and said, In dreams you imagine things, and you
believe that they are real and genuine so long as you are in the dream-state;
but when you wake, you know that what you have been imagining has no basis in
reality. How are you sure of the real existence of all that you believe in your
waking state through sense or reason? It is true in relation to your present
state; but another state may come upon you, whose relation to your present
waking state is like the relation of that state to the dream state; in short,
your present state will be like a dream in relation to that state. If this
state comes, you will be certain that all your rational suppositions are
baseless imaginings. Perhaps this is the state of the Sufis in which they
claim that they see things which are not in accordance with rational
principles. Perhaps this state is death, and perhaps this life is a dream in
relation to the life to come, so that, when a man dies, things will become
apparent to him which are contrary to
what he now observes.
When these thoughts occurred to
me, I tried to find a remedy for them, but it was not easy. They could not be
disproved, for a proof has to be based on first principles, and here it was the
truth of first principles which was in question. The illness proved a difficult
one. It lasted almost two months. During this time I was a sceptic in fact,
though not in outward expression. Then God healed me from this disease. My self
was restored to a sound and balanced condition. The necessary truths of reason
became once again accepted and trusted in with complete certainty. That did not
come about through proof or argument, but by a light which God cast into my
breast; that light is the key to most knowledge. To suppose that the
understanding of profound truth rests upon marshalled arguments is to narrow
unduly the broad mercy of God. As Muhammad said, `God created the creatures in
darkness, and later sprinkled on them some of his light. It is from this light
that deep understanding must be sought. That light floods out from the Divine
generosity at certain times, and one must be on the watch for it.
The point of this narrative is
to show that one has gone to the utmost in seeking truth, when one stops short
of first principles. First principles are not to be sought, since they are
already present; and when what is present is sought, it becomes lost and hidden.
If a man only looks for what may properly be looked for, he cannot be accused
of falling short in the quest for truth.
The first thing to be said in
considering this account of an attack of scepticism is that Deliverance from Error, though
autobiographical, is not strictly an autobiography. In particular, it cannot be
accepted as an accurate chronological record of events. Immediately after the
long passage which has just been paraphrased, al-Ghazali says he now regarded
the seekers after truth as divided into four groups, theologians, Batinites,
philosophers and Sufis; and he proceeded to study the views of each group
thoroughly in order to arrive at truth for himself. This must be a literary
fiction a convenient framework for a schematic presentation of his
conclusions. It seems unlikely that the period of scepticism occurred at an
early stage in his theological studies. It seems certain that the fit of
scepticism as he describes it must have been preceded by some study of
philosophy. It is also clear that he had contacts with mysticism at a
comparatively early period.32 Thus the plan of Deliverance from Error must be regarded as schematic and not
chronological. There is no reason, however, to doubt that he had an actual
experience such as he describes. What we cannot say is that it came early in
his career; it may well have been about the time of his move to Baghdad in
1091, since we know that it was shortly after this that he was engaged in the
intensive study of philosophy. It is also probable that his experience led him
to a complete reappraisal of all the departments of his knowledge.
That al-Ghazalis scepticism had
a philosophical background is shown
by the fact that he links it up with a consideration of the nature of knowledge
and certainty. Some of his arguments bear a close resemblance to those used,
albeit for another purpose, by Miskawayh
(d. 1030). The latter speaks of the judgement of sense by
reason, and among the examples he includes that of the sun, which is known by
rational proofs to be a hundred and sixty odd times greater than the earth.33
It is not necessary to maintain that al-Ghazali had read this particular
passage, though he may well have done so. This passage shows that one of the
points made by al-Ghazali was being discussed by philosophers in the Islamic
world shortly before his time. Apart from this specific evidence, the critique
of knowledge is an aspect of philosophy. The Platonic tradition, too, which was
so strong in the Arabic-writing philosophers, has suggestions of a sphere above
reason, or at least above ordinary mundane reason.34
The reason which al-Ghazali is
criticizing is primarily reason in its theological use. This is indicated by
the example he uses of a man trying to prove that three is more than ten by
performing a miracle. This was exactly the argument used by Islamic theology. A
prophet, according to the theologians, comes to his people with a message from
God, and says to them, This is a message from God, and the proof that it is
from God is that such and such a miracle will happen. The underlying idea is
that a miracle, since it involves a breach in the order of nature, can only be
produced by supernatural power. God produces breaches of the normal order to
substantiate the claims of genuine prophets sent by himself; but if anyone
falsely claims to have a message from God, it will not be substantiated by a
miracle.3S In other words, al-Ghazalis scepticism must have been due in part
to a realization that the rational arguments at the foundation of Islamic theology
were not fully rational, but rested on many assumptions which could not be
rationally justified. Until this time al-Ghazali must have thought of reason as
being exemplified above all in theology, not philosophy. In his book The Aims of the Philosophers, in which
he gave an objective statement of their doctrines without criticism, he has a
revealing sentence to the effect that
there is nothing in the conclusions of solid geometry and arithmetic which is
contrary to reason .3b For a philosophically-minded person these would have been the most prominent
examples of the use of reason! What he means is that mathematical propositions
are not contrary to rational theology. Did this scepticism about reason in its
theological use also extend to it in its philosophical use? Whether it did so
or not during the two months crisis we cannot be sure, but it is not
impossible that his doubts were about reason in all its uses. The remarks at
the end of the passage quoted about looking only for what may properly be looked
for, suggest familiarity with the syllogism and with the fact that the first
premisses of a series of syllogisms cannot be syllogistically proved. In due
course, as we know from the passage about philosophy in Deliverance from Error, he came to see that the metaphysical and
theological aspects of philosophy are far from satisfying the canons of strict
demonstration set up by the logicians. Thus, whatever the relative dating, his
scepticism was eventually turned against philosophy as well as theology.
A similar conclusion is reached
by another line of approach. The question may be asked whether there was ever a
time when al-Ghazali was tempted to abandon theology for philosophy. The
process of answering it will lead into a consideration of some of the more
profound implications of his scepticism.
The attraction of philosophy at
that period might be compared to that of science at the present time. One
outstanding difference was that, whereas our science has had to cut itself
adrift from much of the philosophical tradition of Europe, science in the
Islamic world was intimately associated with the most coherent philosophical
system of the day. Medicine and astronomy astrology were important in practical
life, and logical theory could not but appeal, even if only aesthetically, to
argumentative theologians. Thus there could be no question of abandoning these
sciences altogether. The dual system of education, however, tended to make men
either predominantly Greek in their outlook and adherents of philosophy or
else predominantly Islamic and largely ignorant of Greek learning. There was
little interaction between the two intellectual traditions. Up to this time
there had been only a partial infusion of Greek thought into Islamic
theology-that effected by the great Mu`tazilites about the time of al-Ma mun (regnabat 813-833). What was
then assimilated had been retained by the theologians, but they had done little
to come to terms with the much more fully developed philosophy of al-Farabi and
Avicenna. At most some of them, probably including al-Juwayni, had read a few
books.
The philosophers, on the other
hand, as we have seen, had completely accepted the Islamic state and given it a
place in their system. If we may trust al-GhazAlis expositions of their
arguments, they frequently supported their statements by quotations from the
Qur an; 7 and they were prepared to allow the scholar jurists a function as
mediators between the prophet and the ordinary people.38 Even with
all this, however, there was a deep inner contradiction in their view. Avicenna
went so far as to say that the transcendent faculty (quwwa qudsiyya) of the prophet is the highest of the grades of
the human faculties; 39 and this seems to imply that the prophet is
the summit of human achievement. Yet the philosophical dogma of the supremacy
of reason is in conflict with this. If reason is supreme, how can the prophet
rather than the philosopher be the ideal man? If the prophet is supreme, how
can philosophical reason presume to sit in judgement on his words? As
al-Ghazali remarks, the philosopher has succumbed to false pride in his
achievements in supposing that divine things can be absolutely subject to his
thought and imagination 40 The contradiction is also seen in the fact that the
whole texture of the life of the state is governed by Islamic ideas. There are
indeed Greek ethical works in Arabic (such as that of Miskawayh), but the
Greek ethico-political system was far from providing a viable alternative to
the actual Islamic system.
Thus philosophical reason,
despite its claims, was not really an alternative to the corpus of Islamic
thought. Al-Ghazali, educated in the latter, cannot but have felt this.
These deeper reasons probably
influenced al-Ghazali most, but there were also more superficial ones. The
philosophers were a small coterie-almost of cranks and eccentrics, had it not
been that some were excellent physicians. They were divided among themselves.
Even if some had high offices in political administration, they had little influence
as a group. Many good Muslims looked on them with profound suspicion, and even
attacked reputable theologians for meddling with their books.4 Only with very
strong motives could a theologian have defied this heritage of suspicion and
joined the ranks of the philosophers. All in all, it seems most unlikely that
al-Ghazali was ever seriously tempted to leave theology for philosophy.
From all this it follows, if the
argument is sound, that at the root of al-Ghazalis scepticism was a largely
unconscious disquiet with something in the contemporary condition of rational
theology. At most philosophy had contributed to increase the disquiet, and to
focus it on the imperfect rationality of theology. But there must have been
something in theology itself, or in the theologians, that first made it
possible for al-Ghazali to entertain such doubts. He had been trained to expect
a career as a scholar-jurist (that of a theologian was merely a branch of this
general career-he also wrote one or two books on law). His scepticism must
therefore mean that he had grave doubts about the career. Was it due to some
weakness in himself? Not unless too great honesty for coping with a wicked
world is a weakness. What happened later, however, and an analysis of his
criticisms of the scholar-jurists of his day, makes it clear that it was
nothing personal that made him a sceptic.
The full examination of this
matter belongs to a later chapter. Here some preliminary points may be noted.
Let it be assumed that the source of al-Ghazalis disquiet was the failure in
some respects (not yet specified) of the scholar-jurists. As a zealous young
man connected with the movement of religious revival (in an external sense)
directed by Nizam-al-Mulk, he would wonder how this state of things could be
improved, and he would find the resources of the theological tradition very
meagre. His scepticism may be seen as a realization of the inability of reason
(or human planning) to set things right. It is in accordance with this
interpretation that the solution of the crisis, as; he describes it, is found
by no human effort but comes from alight which God cast into my breast. Man
does what he can, but realizes his inability to proceed, and then, as he pauses
baffled, something beyond himself sets his feet on a new path forward. Just
what the light was, al-Ghazali does not say. In another passage of Deliverance from Error, however, he says
that when he approached the study of Sufism
he already had a settled belief in God, prophethood and the Last Day.42
This is probably not the precise form in which the illumination ending his
scepticism came to him, but it may be the working out of that illumination.
There are various
other small indications that al-Ghazalis disquiet was essentially a feeling
that his civilization was facing a crisis and the solution was neither to hand
nor obvious. When he had recovered from his scepticism, he began a quest for
truth by examining the teachings of the four main groups of seekers for
truth; he thereby implied that both he and they lacked some important aspect
of truth. The title of his book, Deliverance
from Error, has presumably a social as well as an individual reference, and
carries the implication that the community has somehow gone astray. And it
would not be out of place to note here that the title of his greatest book, The Revival of the Religious Sciences, presumes
some decadence or decay in these sciences. It is a major aim of this study to
try to discover in what this decadence consisted.
Perhaps enough has been said to
show how al-Ghazali was involved in the tensions of his time. The one under
consideration in this chapter is that between the two rival educational
systems, each trying to provide the ideational basis for the whole community.
Each had many good points and also some practical weaknesses. Ultimately what
was good in them was complementary, but each tended to claim to be
self-sufficient and to belittle or reject the contribution of its rival. Al-Ghazali did not attempt to escape from this tension. On the contrary he
entered more fully into it, until he felt it deeply within himself. The period
of scepticism is the internal aspect of the process of resolving the external
tension by entering into it. By his voluntary act of accepting this and other
tensions into himself al-Ghazali was able to achieve a resolution of the
tensions which affected the ~ whole subsequent history of Islam.
4 THE INCONSISTENCY OF THE
PHILOSOPHERS
At the end of the previous
chapter al-Ghazalis life-story was taken up to the point of his arrival in
Baghdad in July 1091. He then became immersed in his teaching duties, and seems
to have been a popular lecturer, for at one time (he tells us in Deliverance from Error) he had an
audience of three hundred students. We hear of him taking part in the usual
official functions 43 Yet he also found time to obtain a real grasp of the
Islamic version of Neoplatonic philosophy and the associated sciences. He did
this, too, merely by private reading without any personal contact with
philosophers. He was satisfied with his understanding of the subject in less
than two years, but in addition he spent nearly a year in reflection on it,
doubtless deciding what points in it could be accepted by a theologian and what
points had to be reected.44 It cannot have been till towards the end of the
period of reflection that he began to write the two books to be considered
here. The first, The Aims of the
Philosophers, was a factual and objective account of the doctrines of the
Islamic Neoplatonists, following Avicenna for the most part; the second
contained his criticisms of the philosophers and was entitled The Inconsistency of the Philosophers.45 One
manuscript has a note according to which the book was finished in January 1095;
and there is no good reason for rejecting this.46 If we allow six
months for the writing of the two books-which may be too much he must have
finished his time of reflecting on philosophy by July 1094. But, as he spent
nearly three years between studying and reflecting, the study must have begun
soon after he reached Baghdad in July 1091. That is to say, most of the
four years he spent at Baghdad as a professor was spent in either studying or
writing about philosophy. This does not, of course, exclude his having had some
previous acquaintance with philosophy, especially logic. What he aimed at
acquiring in his studies in Baghdad was a knowledge, especially of logic,
physics and metaphysics, comparable to that of the exponents of these sciences.
When The Inconsistency of the Philosophers is read in the light of what
was said in the previous section, the purpose is clear. As he himself puts it,
the aim is to show your inability to make good your claims to knowledge of the
truth of things by apodeictic proofs, and to make you doubtful of your claims
.47 In other words, he is pursuing the critique of reason which underlay his
bout of scepticism, and is trying to show that reason is not self-sufficient in
the field of metaphysics and is unable out of itself to produce a complete
world-view. Of the twenty theses for which al-Ghazali argues in the book, some
concern positive philosophical doctrines which he rejects, but seven consist in
proving that doctrines held by the philosophers (and sometimes also held by
al-Ghazali) cannot be demonstrated by reason. Reason by itself, he argues,
cannot prove that the world has a creator, that two gods are impossible, that
God is not a body, that He knows both others and Himself, and that the soul is
a self-subsistent entity.48
In all this al-Ghazali was not simply
a sceptic, as has sometimes been alleged, though he frankly admits that he is
not arguing for any positive views, but has the negative aim of showing that
the philosophers are not free from inconsistency and self-contradiction 49 This
limitation of aim is very understandable in his situation. He had come to the
conviction that reason is not self sufficient in either theology or philosophy,
but is in a sense subordinate to a light from God shed in the heart which is
somehow connected with the light given to men by prophetic revelations. He had
only begun, however, the arduous process of giving this conviction a
satisfactory intellectual expression. The negative aim of The Inconsistency of the Philosophers was a necessary
preparation for the erection of a building-a clearing of the site-but the
ultimate building was not yet planned in details.
The thirteen theses
where al-Ghazali rejects doctrines of the philosophers lead us into a different
realm. On three points-the assertion that the world is everlasting, the denial
that God knows particulars, and the denial of bodily resurrection-he adjudges
them to be infidels, outside the community of Islam, though on the other points
he regards them as merely heretical, that is, as holding views which are mistaken
but not so badly mistaken as to exclude from the community.51 The thirteen
points fall roughly into three groups.
The first and largest group is
that associated with the philosophers assertion that the world is everlasting,
in the sense of having no beginning. Al-Ghazali also rejects the further
assertions that the world has no end, that the several heavens are living
creatures and move by will, that they have a definite goal towards which they
move, that their souls know particulars, and that miracles, or breaches of the
course of nature, are impossible. He also accuses them of confusion in
describing the proceeding or emanating of the world from God as his creating it. 52 The last point shows what had
been happening. The philosophers had been adapting Neoplatonic cosmology to
Quranic conceptions by equating emanation with creation. This enabled them to
say that, though the world had no beginning in time, God was its ground from
whom it derived its existence, and in that sense its creator. All Quranic references
to creation were therefore to be interpreted in accordance with this account.
The fundamental cleavage between
Sunnite Islam and the philosophers was probably that the Sunnites wanted to
regard ultimate reality as analogous to a human will, whereas the philosophers
conceived of it rather as an impersonal force. One of al-Ghazalis complaints is that the philosophers make the world
come forth from God by some kind of necessity.S3 The same belief in impersonal
necessity leads them to deny the possibility of miracles. They make allowance
for something analogous to will and other human qualities by ascribing them to
the different heavens; but al-Ghazalihas little difficulty in showing that this
is merely hypothetical. He is, of
course, no crude anthropomorphist. The question at issue between him and the
philosophers is whether the ground of all being is more adequately described by
human analogies or by analogies from natural forces.
The same opposition appears in
the second group. This consists in the philosophers assertion that God knows
only universals and not particulars, and in other assertions involving the
conception of God as bare simplicity, namely, that he has no attributes
distinct from his essence, that the distinction between genus and differentia
does not apply to him, and that he is bare existence without any quiddity or
definite character.54 Now the conception of God as absolute simplicity, with no
special relation to particulars, fits in well with the analogy of a natural
force. The force of gravity bears upon a body only in respect of the universal
features of weight or mass, not in respect of any particular features apart
from these, still less in respect of what makes a man a unique human person.
The question of Gods attributes had been earlier discussed between the main
body of the Sunnites and the sect of the Mutazilites. The latter, theologians
influenced by philosophy, were of a rationalistic turn of mind and denied that
such attributes as knowing, hearing, seeing, speaking, willing, had any
distinct existence within Gods essence. They seem to have been exalting
rational tidiness over the richness of religious experience; and in the long
run it was the religious experience of ordinary men that triumphed.
The third group consists of the
belief that there is no resurrection of bodies, but only a purely spiritual
resurrection of souls (with the corollary that there are no bodily pains and
pleasures in the future life), and the accompanying belief that souls are
naturally immortal. Here we are dealing not with two rival accounts of ultimate
reality but with two rival views of human nature. The philosophers held the
dualistic or Greek view, according to which man consists of soul and body,
but the essential man is the soul, and the body only the souls temporary
garment or, as some extremists put it, its tomb. The contrasting monistic or
Semitic view is that, even if a distinction is allowed between body and soul,
the body is just as much the man as the soul.
In all these disputed matters there are seen to be two main points of difference between al-Ghazali and the philosophers, namely, the application of personal or impersonal analogies to God and the adoption of a monistic or dualistic view of man. In a sense these are basic categories of thought, which are taken for granted throughout civilizations. This is especially true of the second. It is the way in which people think about man throughout a culture, and is perhaps largely determined by which language they use. It is pre-religious in the sense that the founder of a religion expresses his new religious message in terms of the categories of thought employed by the people he is addressing. Muhammads essential message could presumably have been expressed in terms of a dualistic or of a monistic anthropology; but, since the Arabs already thought monistically, he expressed. his message in monistic terms, although the monistic conception of man was not part of his message.
Although categories of thinking
such as we have here might be supposed to be objective, there is an element of
value about them, and it is proper to examine their social relevance. This is
not the place for a full examination of this matter, however, since it would
require a wide investigation of the whole earlier history of the Middle East
and perhaps further afield. In such an examination the kind of hypothesis to be
tested would be, for instance, that the tendency to conceive of ultimate
reality as analogous to natural forces is characteristic of agriculturalists, who
depend on the regularity of the seasons, whereas the tendency to use personal
analogies would be frequent among people like Arabian nomads who find nature
irregular and whose tribes prosper or decline according to the quality of the
human material. For the conceptions of man a hypothesis worth examining would
be that the monistic view of man belonged to people who accepted life and were
moderately satisfied with it, whereas the dualistic one found favour rather
among those who were, on the whole, dissatisfied.54a An alternative would be
that the monistic conception corresponded to emphasis on the community, the
dualistic to exaggeration of the importance of the individual at the expense of
the community.
These particular issues of the
eleventh-century caliphate are not altogether dead in the West of our own day.
Modern science has emphasized the extent of law in nature, so that we tend to
think of ultimate reality as impersonal and find it difficult to fit in the
personal, whether in its religious or in its secular form. In, our
views of man, too, both philosophy and religion, under Greek influence, have
propagated a dualistic outlook, but recently modern science, with psychology in
the van here, has been moving towards a monistic conception. These contemporary
parallels may help us to appreciate the problems confronting al-Ghazali.
The social context in which the
particular categories first appeared is one problem. Another somewhat different
problem is that of their transmission to the Muslims of the eleventh century,
including both the route of the transmission and the motives governing those
who adopted the categories. An important part was played by the conquests of
Alexander the Great, which were followed by the spread of Hellenistic culture
up to the borders of India. The Islamic philosophy we have been considering was
part of this Hellenistic culture, whose tide was now receding. The Quranic
categories, again, were taken over by the non-Arab Muslims of the caliphate
along with the Islamic religion. They seem to have been whole-heartedly
accepted, even although many of the new Muslims had had very different
categories previously. This is one of the remarkable features of the situation.
In the more strictly religious field, when new ideas are adopted along with a
new religion, there tends to be also some recrudescence of old ideas, perhaps
after an interval; an example is the idea of the charismatic leader among the
Shiite Muslims, who give it a prominence unjustified by the Quran. In the case
of the monistic view of man, perhaps it was widely accepted because it was
assumed or taken for granted rather than explicitly taught-and so slipped in
unnoticed-and because it did not obviously thwart any deep religious
conviction.
Yet another question worth asking
is whether the adoption of the Quranic categories by the non-Arab Muslims has
had any independent influence on their outlook and attitudes. To superficial
observation Muslims certainly seem to be more conscious than Westerners of the
human aspect and to be much less impersonal in their dealings with human
beings; but this fact, if it is one, may be due not to these categories of
thought, but to their being closer to pre-industrial society.
However fascinating such speculations may be, the primary purpose here is to consider al-Ghazalis response to the situation in which he found himself, where there was strong tension between two sets of categories. Without hesitation he accepts the Quranic and rejects the philosophical at the various points of conflict which he mentions. He was following his teacher, al-Juwayni, in adhering to the religion of the old women. He would not even allow the philosophers to say, as al-Farabi had said, that the Quranic conceptions were symbolic ones, put forward for the sake of ordinary men who could not comprehend the more abstract language of philosophy.55 To allow this would have been to allow a certain inferiority to be attached to the Quranic conceptions. If revelation is ultimate, however, reason cannot be permitted to whittle away its supremacy in this fashion. Yet despite this decision al-Ghazali had been deeply influenced by his philosophical studies. His conception of man (and of the soul) becomes more and more complex as he tries to combine something of both conceptions. In general he was prepared to accept the findings of the Greek sciences wherever they did not conflict with religion; for some parts of them, such as the logical doctrine of the syllogism, he became an enthusiast. In the next section we shall consider in detail how much philosophy he was prepared to accept.
5. THE
INTRODUCTION OF LOGIC INTO THEOLOGY
The tension which al-Ghazali
found in his environment and into which he entered more fully by a deliberate
decision was due to the separation between two disciplines which really
belonged together, namely, the Islamic sciences of the scholar-jurists and the
foreign sciences of the philosophers. As already noted, there had been
remarkably little contact between the two sets of intellectuals. The philosophers
had fully accepted the existence of the Islamic state, founded by a prophet
statesman, but they had made no allowance in their systems for the fact that in
its details the life of the Islamic community depended on a revelation or
revealed-law (sharia) and that for
the proper application of this revelation there had to be a special class of
interpreters of it, the scholar-jurists. The philosophers had also made no
effort to disseminate their sciences widely. They had had few living contacts
with the scholar jurists, they had presented a subject like logic in an
unnecessarily strange technical vocabulary which made it incomprehensible to
the average scholar-jurist, and they had strongly suggested that acceptance of
any part of their sciences included acceptance of the whole-and this whole
included some dubious theological views. The scholar-jurists, for their part,
had accepted that amount of Greek philosophy which had been assimilated by the
Mu`tazilites in the first half of the ninth century, but had paid no further
attention to it. So the two streams had gone their separate ways, and there was
now a heritage of suspicion to be overcome.
By the
eleventh century the scholar-jurists were realizing that there was much of
value in the foreign sciences. There are various references to individual
scholars reading some of the books of thephilosophers,56 but owing
to the widespread popular and scholarly suspicion of the philosophers it was
difficult for any scholarjurist to refer to any philosophical work in his
writings. What made it possible for al-Ghazali to break new ground here was
doubtless the support of the Seljuq government for the Asharites and its need
for an intellectual defence of the Sunnite position against Shiite, especially
Ismailite, propaganda. The extent of the connection between Isma`ilism and
philosophy is notclear,57 but a popular belief in such a connection, even if
mistaken, would be a sufficient justification for al-Ghazali to publish his
books on The Aims of the Philosophers and The Inconsistency of the Philosophers.
What in
effect al-Ghazali did was to examine the philosophical sciences to see how much
of them was valuable as an addition to the Islamic sciences and how much had to
be rejected. As a scholar-jurist he was interested in logical questions, since
legal discussions sometimes involved these;58 and for years he was
very enthusiastic about logic. His conclusions about the value of the
philosophical sciences as given in
Deliverance from Error,59 written about i rob, are the results of his
mature reflection. He regards the philosophical sciences as six in number,
namely, mathematics, logic, natural science, theology (or metaphysics),
politics and ethics.
Mathematics is entirely true,
he holds, but the contemporary teaching of it (by the philosophers) is attended
by two drawbacks: the students of mathematics tend to think that all the
philosophers arguments are as cogent as their mathematical ones, and ignorant
opponents of mathematics from a religious standpoint bring religion in general
into disrepute. Logic is likewise true and not contrary to religion in any way,
but has the same two drawbacks as mathematics. Natural science or physics need
not in general be rejected from the standpoint of religion, but some
conclusions of the philosopher-physicists, as enumerated in The Inconsistency, are to be rejected.
In theology or metaphysics the philosophers differ from one another and have
many errors. These fall under twenty heads (as in The Inconsistency), of which three constitute unbelief and the rest
heresy. (This is not quite correct, since, as was noticed above, some of the
seventeen points consist not in false or objectionable doctrines, but in the
philosophers inability to prove rationally points that they claim to prove
thus.) Their discussion of politics
is merely utilitarian. Their ethics contains sound principles derived from
prophets and mystics, together with worthless ideas of their own, and is
therefore liable to mislead.
Al-Ghazalis
attitude to the philosophers ethics is in strong contrast to his attitude to
their mathematics, logic and physics. There are traces, however, of a more
favourable attitude to philosophical ethics at an earlier period. At the end of
an exposition of Aristotelian logic (probably written in 1095) he said he was
about to write a complementary work on The
Criterion of Action.6o A work with this title has in fact been
preserved, some of which is almost certainly genuine, though other parts are
definitely not by al-Ghazali 6 The genuine part would appear to be an attempt
to develop the Aristotelian conception of virtue as a mean, and would clearly
be complementary to the logical work. Soon after writing it, however-if indeed
he ever completed it to his satisfaction-he must have turned to a complete rejection
of the criterion of the mean as a scientific basis for ethics. The condemnation
of philosophical ethics in Deliverance
from Error is paralleled by the absence of references to The Criterion of Action in his own later
works62 Perhaps at the time of his realization that the strict demands of logic
were not fulfilled by philosophical theology, he came to see that the same was
true of ethics, and in ethics as in theology turned back to the Islamic
revelation.
His
rejection of ethics makes his extensive writing on logic all the more
significant. There are some seventy pages about it in The Aims of the Philosophers, two fuller expositions for serious
students, a more popular defence of it ostensibly directed against the
Batinites, and some slighter references. When this activity of composition is
connected with his remarks about the danger of innocent students thinking that
all the works of the philosophers were as carefully argued as their logical
works, it would seem that he aimed at making available for such students books
on logic which were not by philosophers but reached the same standard of
technical competence as the philosophers writings. The provision of an account
of the philosophical sciences not by a philosopher may also have been part of
his aim in writing The Aims of the
Philosophers. This would help to explain the curious procedure of writing a
separate book about the opponents views before criticizing them. He thus laid
himself open to the charge of disseminating knowledge of heretical views and
perhaps misleading the unwary; but he probably felt that it was worth taking
this risk in order that students following the normal curriculum might have a
chance of learning about logic and physics from a source independent of the philosophers.
The two
main logical works, The Standard for
Knowledge and The Touchstone of
Thinking, are intended for persons educated in the scholar-jurist
tradition. In the first he says he is writing to explain the methods of
reasoning and to keep the promise made in The
Inconsistency. There he had used the technical terms of the philosophers
without explanation, since he was writing primarily for philosophers; now he
wants to address those not familiar with philosophical books and to show them
what the terms mean. The same rules apply to arguments both in philosophical or
rational matters (`agliyydt)
and in legal matters (fighiyyat); and
therefore, to make the subject easier for scholar-jurists, he will take the
examples from their field 63
While
the purpose of these two works is readily understandable, that of The Just Balance, the work directed
against the Batinites, is obscure. What is puzzling is that much of the work
consists in somewhat forced interpretations of Quranic passages to find a
justification for the various types of syllogism. A quotation will illustrate
his method of procedure:
The higher criterion is the
criterion of Abraham (God bless and preserve him) which he used against Nimrod;
from it we learn this criterion, yet by means of the Quran. Nimrod claimed
divinity, and divinity for him, as all agree, was an expression for having
power over everything. Abraham said, My God is God because he causes to live
and to die, and has power over that, and you have no power for that. I do cause
to live and to die, he replied, meaning that he caused to live through seed in
intercourse and to die through killing. Abraham realized that it was difficult
to make him understand the invalidity of this argument, and turned to what
would be clearer for him. `He said, God brings the sun from the east, so do you
bring it from the west; the unbeliever was confounded (z.z58/26o). God then
praised Abraham and said, `And that proof of ours We gave Abraham against his
people (6. 83). From this I came to see that the proof and demonstration was
in what Abraham said and his criterion. I reflected on the manner of his using
it, as you might reflect on the criterion of gold and silver. I saw that this
proof had two bases, which were married to one another; from the union is born
a conclusion, the knowledge gained. For the Quran is founded on omission and
compression. The full form of this criterion is to say: `Everyone who is
capable of causing the sun to rise is God-one base; My God is the (one)
capable of causing it to rise-the other base; from the combination of the two
it follows that My god is God, and not you, Nimrod 64
The passage concludes with an examination of the source
of our knowledge of the premisses.
Now it may be admitted that a syllogism is implicit in the verses of
the Quran, but why should it be necessary to argue about it like this? Why
should a man like al-Ghazali, capable of writing a full technical exposition of
Aristotelian logic, spend time on trivialities of this kind? Obviously because
some people who could not understand the technicalities needed to be assured
that logic was based on the Qur an. There were many people of this kind until
long after al-Ghazali, even people who rejected geometry.65 The
heart of the problem, however, is why a book against the Batinites should
envisage readers of this outlook and level of education, for the Batinites are
usually said to have had close connections with certain strands of the
philosophical movement. In trying to solve the problem it has to be remembered
that the Batinite propaganda had many faces, and tended to become all things to
all men. It has also to be remembered that a polemical work may be intended to
confirm waverers in ones own ranks rather than to convince the opponents. All
that can be done here is to make the general statement that Batinite teaching
must have been proving attractive to simple-minded people loyal to the Quran.66
The achievement of al-Ghazali in his encounter with philosophy has
left a mark on the whole subsequent course of Islamic thought. He gave theology
a philosophical foundation, and also made possible an undue intellectualization
of it, though he is not to be blamed if later theologians have gone to excess
in their philosophizing. These points will be further considered in the last
chapter.
IV
TRUTH
FROM THE CHARISMATIC LEADER
INTRODUCTORY
NOTE
Of the
four groups of people with whom al-Ghazali had to come to terms, the second to
be considered here is the one he calls the Talimites, the party of
authoritative instruction. This is a section or aspect of the political and
religious movement known as Ismailism; or, to be more precise, al-Ghazali
appears to apply the term Td limites to those adherents of the Ismailite
movement who laid special emphasis on the doctrine of taiim or authoritative instruction.
When he is referring to the movement in a more general way he usually speaks of
the Batinites, the people of the datin or
esoteric meaning. The movement has also several other names, but these properly
indicate distinct parts of it, since it is a highly complex phenomenon. who
were adherents of Batinism or likely to be influenced by it were also deeply
attached to the Quran that al-Ghazali (as noted at the end of the previous
chapter) in writing The Just Balance against
the Batinites had to claim that logical theory was derived from the Quran.
Those initiated into the higher grades of the movement, however-at least in
some periods and in some parts of the Islamic world-held philosophical views
about the equivalence of all religions which
practically placed them outside the community of Muslims. To what extent
these leaders seriously considered abandoning the Islamic community (or should
we say abandoning an Islamic basis for the community?) we shall probably
never know for certain. They were undoubtedly hostile to Islam as Nizam-al-Mulk
conceived it, and in their doctrines they had an instrument that could be used
for its destruction.
The
flexibility in propaganda was something which had developed gradually.
Originally there had been a definite ideational basis, since Ismailism was a
branch of Shiism and had much in common with the other branches. While it has
sometimes been held that the earliest Shiites were Arabs who supported Ali for
political reasons, careful study of the sources suggests that from the first
some of the followers of Ali were seeking in him an embodiment of the
archetype or dynamic image of the charismatic leader.3 A survey of the whole
history of Shtism further suggests that, though it has had political
implications, it has always been primarily a religious movement, and that its
purely political ideas have never been sufficiently good as political ideas to
arouse the devotion that has been manifested. Politically it has stood for
autocracy, perhaps at times for a benevolent autocracy giving full
consideration to the interests of the lower classes; and for some adherents
this political appeal may have been uppermost. Essentially, however, what the
various branches of Shi ism have in common is not the political principle of
autocracy but the fundamentally religious quest for the charismatic leader.
Some of the phenomena where politics seem to predominate are to be interpreted
as the attempts of politicians, whether sincere or unscrupulous, to make use for
their political ends of this deep religious yearning.
The
Isma`ilite branch of Shi`ism seems to have separated from the main body about
765. It receives its name from recognizing as imam the previous imams son
Ismail instead of another son Musa who was recognized by the main body. For
the next century and a half the history is obscure, and there are important
disagreements among historians. It became more associated with revolutionary
bodies and ideas than other branches of Shi ism. Shortly before goo there was a
resurgence of Isma ilism, as a result of which an Isma ilite dynasty known as
the Fatimids was established in Tunisia in qoq. In 969 this dynasty
conquered Egypt, and shortly afterwards founded Cairo as their capital. Because
of their Isma°ilite conception of the imam of the Muslim community the
Fatimids, unlike other powerful provincial dynasties, did not recognize the
nominal suzerainty of theAbbasid caliphs. On the contrary, they themselves
claimed to be the rightful caliphs of the whole Islamic world, and they
organized a propaganda machine (dawa) and
sent agents (sing. ddi) throughout
the Abbasid domains to disseminate their teachings and make contact with
discontented and dissident groups.
Because of the
flexibility already noted the Fatimid agents were very successful in making
contacts and gaining adherents. Possibly the reason for Nizam-alMulk not
mentioning any revolts after 975 is that any subsequent revolts were
so clearly connected with the Fatimids that no one would imagine they were
separate.
One of the important groups
which acknowledged the Fatimid rulers as imams were the Qarmatians or
Carmathians of Bahrein, who ruled a small state on the Persian Gulf.4The
Brethren of Purity (Ikhwan as-Safa) in Basra, a coterie of philosophers and
natural scientists with Neopythagorean leanings, also gave some degree of
allegiance to the Fatimids and probably made an important contribution to the
ideational basis s
This
is, of course, not a complete account of the successes of the Fatimid propagandists
in the Abbasid caliphate, but only an indication of the complexity of the
story. Another aspect of this complexity is revealed in the attempt to discover
the identity of the supporters of the movement. It is commonly held that the
Ismailites were the political party of the labouring and artisan class in their
struggle against the upper class .6 There is probably much truth in this view,
but it is not easy to square it with some important materials. It could perhaps
be said to be implicit in Nizam-al-Mulks account of the Batinites, but he only
speaks of leaders who are courtiers and administrators. In the Mustalhiri, the book dedicated to the
caliph al-Mustazhir, al-Ghazalis peaks of eight classes of persons who
are attracted by the movement:? (I) people with a tendency to deify men (such
as Ali); (2) Persian nationalists seeking to recover autonomy; (3) men seeking
power or vengeance; (4) people who think themselves superior to the masses and
seek something strange and unusual; (f) superficial and dilettante members of
philosophical coteries; (6) atheistic philosophers and dualists; (7) people of
Shi ite tendencies who are sympathetic to Batinite teaching; (8) men dominated
by their passions who find the religious law irksome. Now some of these categories
might include labourers and artisans, but several exclude these. The Brethren
of Purity come in the sixth group, and some perhaps also in the fifth. The
explanation and expansion of all these statements would require a long
investigation; but even without expansion they illustrate the complexity of the
movement.
In the
troubled years after the fall of the Buwayhid dynasty of Baghdad in 1015 the Fatimids achieved their most
successful penetration of the Abbasid realm. A Turkish general was won over to
their cause after the fall of his Buwayhid masters, and was able to occupy
Baghdad in their name for nearly a year, so that it was they and not the
Abbasids who were mentioned in the Friday prayers.8 By about 1060,
however, the Seljuq sultan had so consolidated his power with Baghdad as
capital that there was little likelihood of a successful pro-Fatimid
revolution. Egypt began to suffer from internal troubles. The later leader of
the Ismailite movement in Persia, al-Hasan ibn-as-Sabbah, visited Egypt in
1078. Whether or not he was badly treated by one faction, as is sometimes
stated, he must have seen for himself that the Fatimid government was losing
its revolutionary fervour and, besides having little enthusiasm, was no longer
capable of making an effective intervention in the east. On his return to
Persia he spent several years travelling about and organized a revolt that did
not count on Fatimid help. By Logo he was able to seize the fortress of Alamut
in southern Persia; and on October 14, 1092, one of his followers assassinated
Nizam-al-Mulk--one of the first instances of this activity which gets its
English name from a nickname of these Ismalilites, hashish-men, hashshjshin, corrupted to
Assassins.
It is
primarily of these Persian (Khurasanian) Ismailites that al-Ghazali is
thinking when he speaks of Talimites, for his usual phrase is the Batinites
of our time; and in other sources al-Hasan is credited with being the author
ofthe new teachingwhich emphasized talim
or authoritative instruction.,) (The subsequent doctrinal
developments of this branch of Isma`ilism, beginning with their adoption of
Nizar as hidden imam .110 do not
concern a study of al-Ghazali, since they do not appear to have come to the
knowledge of the Sunnite world during his lifetime.) The doctrine of
authoritative instruction, namely, that in order to learn the truth about
anything you have to ask, and be instructed by, the infallible imam, is an
understandable development of earlier Shiism. The Fatimids also had the
principle (if reliance can be placed on a later document), but probably placed
less emphasis on it.
The
essence of Shiism is belief in the imam or charismatic leader, which includes
the belief that salvation, or keeping to the straight path and avoiding error,
comes from following the imam, in contrast to the Sunnite belief that it comes
from being a member of the charismatic community. In keeping with the essential
belief, the imam came to be regarded as a source of truth or guidance for his
followers. This point was involved in the theological discussions in the ninth
century about the createdness of the Quran. By holding that the Quran was the
eternal and untreated Word of God men were insisting that the source of the
beaten path (sunna) or, as we might
say, the way of life of the community was supernatural, and were thereby
justifying Sunnite claims for the community. The Mutazilite and other
upholders of the opposing view that the Quran was created were interested in
placing more emphasis on the charismatic leader, that is, in political terms,
in increasing the powers of the ruler and his advisers and in decreasing those
of the scholar-jurists, the official exponents of the system of law based on
Quranic principles as expanded in Tradition.
Some Ismailite formulations speak of a parallelism of the imam and
the Quran; x but to the detached student this seems to be a sop to
the Sunnite feelings of the masses. The doctrine of authoritative instruction
had as its complement the conception of the esoteric meaning (batin). By this everything in the
Quran (and in the Traditions and religious institutions) had an esoteric
meaning, which bore no necessary resemblance to its plain or exoteric meaning,
and which could only be learnt from the imam. Thus heaven and hell could be
particular men. In this way it was possible to continue to pay lip-service to
the Quran, and yet to ensure that the Quran placed not the slightest check on
the imams control of the ideational basis of the community and therefore of
its whole life. Al-Hasan ibn-as-Sabbah seems to have greatly increased the
emphasis on this aspect of Ismailite teaching by insisting that truth could only be learned from the imam. Personal
effort (Jtihad) in thinking and
reasoning (ray, nalar), he argued,
could not lead to truth, since their exponents were always in disagreement.
This was a direct attack on the scholar-jurists. The promise of unity, too,
must have had a strong appeal for men who remembered the period of anarchy
prior to the Seljuq conquest, and probably looked on political and ideational
disunity as the cause of their sufferings.3
The
nature of Ismailism may best be summarized by considering the relations
between the ruler or government and the intellectuals (the bearers of the ideational
foundation of a movement). In Sunnite Islam in its classical form the ruler had
no control at all over the ideational basis; he could not even legislate in the
strict sense, since all possible legislation was in principle contained in the
Quran and Traditions, and of these the intellectuals, the scholar-jurists,
were the guardians. In the Russian form of Marxism the ruler (Lenin, Stalin,
Khrushchev) has become the controller of the ideational basis of the state,
since only he can give the correct interpretation of Marxist doctrne to meet
the needs of the contemporary situation.13& His control of ideation,
however, is limited by the existence of a corpus of documents-the works of
Marx, Engels and Lenin. In Ismailism even this last limitation has been
removed. Though there is a corpus of documents which has been acknowledged, its
efficacy as a check on the ruler has been destroyed by the conception of the
esoteric meaning. Thus the Ismailism of the Assassins stands for complete
autocracy, in which the whole life of the community is derived from the ruler
in much the same way as all existence emanates from the Neoplatonic One.
2 THE INTELLECTUAL DEFENCE OF SUNNISM
Al-Ghazalis
outlook was close to that of Nizam-alMulk. This may be presumed from his
association with the statesman, but it is also shown by passages in his
writings, such as his repetition of the dictum that religion and government
are twin-brothers.14 He must also have shared the older mans concern about
the growth of Isma ilism, and that concern would not have been lessened by
Nizam-al-Mulks assassination in 1092. He therefore responded with alacrity to
the request of the young caliph al-Mustazhir that he should write a book in refutation of the doctrines of the
Talimites or Batinites. Al-Mustazhir came to the throne on February 7, 1094,
and the book was completed before al-Ghazali left Baghdad in November 1045; it
was probably written during 1095.15 This book is commonly known as the Musta,Ihiri. Al-Ghazali subsequently
wrote several other works directed in whole or in part against the Batinites. The Just Balance, as already noted,
justifies logical principles by reference to the Quran, and must have been
intended for relatively simple-minded believers. A manuscript of one of the
shorter works has been discovered recently,16 but the remainder seem to have
perished.
By
including the Talimites among the four groups of seekers whose works he
studies in his quest for truth (according to the account in Deliverance from Error), al-Ghazali
suggests that the doctrine had some attraction for him. This suggestion is not
to be pressed, however. Deliverance from
Error, as has already been seen, is not a strict autobiography. On general
grounds it seems unlikely that he was ever seriously attracted by the idea of
authoritative instruction. The whole Batinite movement was bitterly hostile to
the class of scholar-jurists to which he belonged (even if he also was critical
of the class). His skill in logic, too, must soon have shown him the weakness
of the Talimite position. His chief aim in studying Talimite doctrine seems
to have been to try to appreciate what it was in it which attracted men.
It is
perhaps appropriate also at this point to notice the suggestion that fear of
the Batinites and of assassination was the main motive of al-Ghazalis actions
at this time.7 This suggestion, too, is to be rejected. Since he had been
prominent as an opponent of the Batinites, he may have had some fear of
assassination; but it is almost certain that assassination had not come to be
thought characteristic of the Assassins in the Baghdad of 1095, since most of
the instances are later. Moreover, al-Ghazali says that it was hell he was
afraid of, not death.Es That indicates a sense that something was wrong with
the quality of his life. To be murdered by a Batinite, on the other hand, would
have been regarded by him as martyrdom and tending to ensure entrance to
paradise. So the arguments against the suggestion are strong; and in the
following chapters it will be shown that there is a satisfying alternative
explanation.
In the Mustajhiri al-Ghazali places
considerable emphasis on the doctrine of authoritative instruction and its
complements-over thirty folios out of just over a hundred-and in Deliverance from Error it is the
main topic to be discussed in connection with the Ta`limites. The emphasis is
justified by the prominence given to the doctrine in the new teaching of
al-Hasan ibn-as-Sabbah. About the time the caliph asked him to write on this
subject, too, he had been very interested in logic, and had been studying it
hard and writing about it. He doubtless felt that this was a field in which he
could easily defeat his opponents, and perhaps impress their
philosophically-minded adherents. Most polemic, of course, though ostensibly
directed against opponents, is really intended to give support to members of
ones own party who are in danger of being convinced by the opponents
arguments. Al-Ghazalis argumentation here would fit in well with this conception.
It shows that, though they profess to abandon reasoning, they cannot avoid
surreptitiously making use of it, and that it is practically impossible to
consult the imam or his representative in every case; he does not attack their
esoteric doctrines. In other words, a large part of al-Ghazalis intellectual
effort is to show the inconsistencies of the Talimites.
There
is an important difference between the MustaIi
iri and Deliverance from Error. The
former, being commissioned by the caliph, naturally has a section proving that
he and not the Fatimid ruler in Cairo is the rightful caliph. This is along the
usual juristic lines, and in accordance with the utilitarian conception of the
imamate held by al-Ghazali.9 By about IIo8, however, when he wrote Deliverance from Error, he had a deeper
appreciation of what lay behind the Batinite movement. He was no longer content
with destructive criticism of his opponents, but had realized that part of
their success was due to the fact that they satisfied, however imperfectly, the deep demand in mens hearts for an
embodiment of the dynamic image of the charismatic leader. So he now insists
that Muslims have such a leader, but that he is Muhammad. He has his living
expositors (presumably the scholar-jurists are meant), just as the hidden imam
has his expositors, the accredited agents. In a sense he is thus carrying the
war into the enemys camp. Yet he has not altogether met the deep need in mens
hearts. To put it in Islamic language, there is always a hope that a hidden
imam may reappear, but there is no hope of the return of Muhammad before the
Last Day. In other words, the desire for a leader is not fully satisfied. In so
far as that is a desire for a leader who is active in the present or who may be
active in the not-too-distant future it is not satisfied. Is it the failure of
Sunnism to satisfy such a desire that has prevented the reunion of Sunnism and
Shi ism?
It is
perhaps worth calling attention here to what al-Ghazali does not say. Though
the `Abbasid caliphs had originally claimed to have charismata, he does not
attempt to make them into imams of the Batinite type. Their position, now shorn
of nearly all real power, would have made this ludicrous. Neither does he
attempt to attribute any charismata to the scholar-jurists, apart from the
vague phrase about the expositors or preachers of Muhammads message, which
does not necessarily refer to them alone or even to them at all. Had he wanted
he could have referred to the Tradition that the scholarjurists were the heirs
of the prophets, but he took such a low view of the condition of the
scholar-jurists in his own day that he understandably passed them over. His
later thought, as we shall see, tended to the view that there was an elite who,
by treading the path of the mystics or Sufis, could obtain an insight into
divine truth comparable to that of the prophets. It is perhaps in parts of his
later works apparently unconnected with contemporary problems that we find his
real and effective answer to the challenge of Isma`ilism, which, even if it had
little effect on the ruling institution, enabled Islamic society to preserve
its characteristic structure and manner of life.
V
THE REAPPRAISAL OF THEOLOGY
INTRODUCTORY NOTE
Al-Ghazali
was by training a jurist and a theologian, and his attitude to these
disciplines must be taken to have had a central place in his development. There
is a tendency among Western scholars to regard Islamic theology as trivial
hair-splitting, and therefore to suppose that in his later period al-Ghazali
felt the same distaste for it that they feel. This is a complete failure to
appreciate what theology meant to him and to men in a similar position.
The
standpoint of this book may be roughly described as that of the sociology of
knowledge. The theologian is looked upon as a type of intellectual with an
important function to perform in the community. Firstly, it is his business to
formulate the objectives of the community and the view of the nature of reality
(including values) associated with these objectives. Secondly, he has to
systematize this ideational basis of the community by smoothing out
discrepancies which lead to tensions, either discrepancies originally present
or those due to novel circumstances; that is to say, in systematizing the ideational
basis of the community he is also adapting it to external changes affecting the
community. If we are to understand the place of al-Ghazali in Islamic theology,
we must have some idea of what had been achieved by earlier theologians.
1 THE
ACHIEVEMENTS OF ISLAMIC THEOLOGY
THE first theological
developments in Islam came after the first wave of conquest had subsided. When
the excitement of advance was over, discontent began to appear, probably mainly
due to the feeling of insecurity consequent upon the revolutionary changes in
the way of life of the Arabs who formed the Muslim armies. This discontent led
to the assassination of the caliph Uthman in 656. In the disturbed conditions
of the following period, when Ali was caliph but not universally recognized,
there appeared the two contrasting sects of the Kharijites and the Shiites.
The
essential feature of the Kharijites was their emphasis on the dynamic idea or
image of the charismatic community, an idea which was implicit in the Quran
and in the life of the Muslim state. Originally, however, the Kharijites
adopted this idea in an unsuitable form. Anyone, they said, who committed a
grave sin, would be punished in Hell, and so belonged to the people of Hell; he
was no longer a believer or member of the Islamic community, and thus there was
no sin in killing him. In practice this meant that small groups of Kharijites,
regarding themselves as saints and all other men as enemies, revolted against
the government (which consisted in their eyes of grave sinners). One of the
important achievements of the theologians, especially those in Basra in the
last half century of Umayyad rule, was to transform this dynamic idea so that
it became applicable to the whole body of Muslims, scattered over what was now
a world empire. They made it possible for Muslims to regard themselves as
belonging to a community that was divinely constituted (and brought important
advantages to its members), yet which did not lose this character through the
sins of some members.
Meanwhile
another group of people, the Shiites, living in the same conditions, tried to
find security by emphasizing the dynamic image of the charismatic leader -the
divinely-sent and divinely-inspired leader who could guide them to safety
through the perils of the world.z There was not much in the Quran about such a
charismatic leader, but Muhammad himself was clearly one. The idea that was
developed, then, was that other members of his family shared in his
divinely-conferred qualities. Though later Shiites came to regard such
charismata as belonging only to descendants of Muhammads cousin and daughter,
Ali and Fatima, in the Umayyad period some men were prepared to allow that the
whole clan of Hashim shared in the charismata. The Abbasid family made claims
embodying this conception, namely, that they were the heirs of the charismata,
and many no doubt believed their claims; but there were also many still
dissatisfied. The numbers and importance of Shiites and Shiite-sympathizers
during the first century of Abbasid rule (75o-85o) is a problem that has not
been adequately studied. The two theological tendencies just described, the
Shiite and what eventually became the Sunnite, appear to be linked up with
political factors, which I have tried to indicate provisionally by speaking of
the autocratic and constitutionalist blocs.3 This contrast and opposition
will appear repeatedly in the following pages.
The
Umayyad period is also noteworthy for raising the problem of human freedom or
responsibility and divine omnipotence or predestination. This again had a
political reference. Is a man
bound to accept an unjust government (such as many held the Umayyad dynasty to
be), or is he free to rebel against
it? For the Kharijites this problem was linked with their conception of the
nature of the community; could the community be a charismatic one if the ruler
was a wrongdoer? The discussion continued well into the Abbasid period, by
which time the political situation was entirely different. The outstanding
protagonists of human freedom were the Mu`tazilites, who had adopted something
of the Greek intellectual outlook, and who linked thee question of mans
freedom with that of Gods justice. In the end the great majority of Muslims,
however, firmly asserted Gods omnipotence. They allowed that man was free, to
a sufficient extent for him to be justly punished for his acts on the Last Day,
but in general they thought that he determined events only within narrow limits
and then subject to Gods will. Perhaps they felt that there was something
inevitable about the Islamic state, or perhaps they merely realized the
limitations of human planning. However that may be, the result was the general
acceptance by Muslims of this element from their Arabian heritage-the sense
that life is determined by forces beyond mans control-and a general rejection
of the Greek conception of freedom.
By
about 8oo the conception of the Sunna had taken shape, and many Muslims were
speaking of themselves as the people of the Sunna. The Sunna may be described
as the divinely-appointed way of life or mores of the community. The conception
developed out of legal discussions about what was right or wrong according to
Islamic principles with regard to certain points. For a time men were content
to say that the view of our school is so-and-so or the view of N (an
important member of the school) was so-and-so. The practice grew up, however,
of supporting particular legal views by anecdotes about something that Muhammad
had said or done, such anecdotes being technically known as Traditions and
being accompanied by an isnad or list
of transmitters. After the work of ash-Shaffi (d. 820) Traditions became the
normal vehicle for legal and other views. Where there was no Tradition or only
an anecdote with an imperfect isnad, it
became necessary to complete the isnad, to
modify an existing Tradition, or even to invent a new one. All the inherited
wisdom of the Middle East, one might almost say, came to be incorporated in
Traditions. Muslim scholars realized that many Traditions were spurious, and
had elaborate rules for the critique of Traditions; but the aim of this
critique was not the establishing of objective truth in a modern sense, but, as
noted above (p. 10), the elimination of the eccentric views of the lunatic
fringe and the retention of views acceptable to the main body of Muslims. This
aim was more or less realized .4
The
conception that thus emerged was that of the Sunna (or beaten path) of the
Prophet, and this was taken to be a form of revelation, roughly on a level with
the Quran itself. This strengthened the belief that the Islamic community was
a charismatic one, since it had a fixed way of life that was God-inspired and
Godgiven. To the modem observer there may appear to be an element of ideology
or distortion in this conception. The Arab contribution to Islamic culture is
greatly exaggerated and that of other peoples neglected. Even if allowance is
made for the mysterious way in which the Arab element has moulded the whole,
there is still exaggeration; and this exaggeration of the Arab contribution
helps us to understand the protest against Arab superiority in the Shut ubite
movement.;
There was one part of the inherited culture of the Middle East which
could not be incorporated into Traditions, and that was philosophy or, to
describe it more accurately, the scientific world-view of the time.
Besides
the philosophical movement within Islam which has been discussed above (in
chapter III) there was in certain Traditionist circles an interest in philosophical
or rational theology, mostly called kalam
(and its practitioners mutakallimun).
This perhaps began about 780. The men who engaged in the new discipline had
different views on various theological questions, but gradually some of the
more outstanding became marked off from the rest not merely by the adoption of
rational methods of argument but also by agreeing about certain dogmatic
positions. This group called themselves the Mutazila, and many Western
scholars, especially in the nineteenth century, found them the most congenial
of Islamic theological schools. As was seen above, they stood for free will
against predestination. They are also noted for insisting that the Quran was
created. These two points are sufficient to show that the Mu tazilites had
adopted not merely Greek methods of rational argument but also certain Greek
conceptions. Indeed, in more ways than can be mentioned here they were trying
to effect some reconciliation between revelation and reason. This was a
political matter, however, as well as an intellectual one. Reason and
philosophy, we saw, tended to be associated with the class of secretaries and
administrators. Revelation, on the other hand, had an obvious connection with
the rising class of Islamic intellectuals, the scholar-jurists or ulema, which
was being formed out of what under the Umayyads had been the pious opposition
and what later became the Traditionist movement. This latter class was the
bearer of the conception of the Sunna, both in general and in detail, and naturally
wanted the community to be based exclusively on the Quran and the Sunna. They
were the main members of what has been called the constitutionalist bloc.
Though the Mutazilites arose out of this class of Islamic intellectuals their
main aim seems
to have been to achieve a wide
synthesis or compromise, and some of them had distinct Shiite sympathies.
Shiism is linked with reason and the autocratic bloc. It has been noticed
how the philosophy of al-Farabi lends itself to be the justification of a
thoroughgoing autocracy, in which the court and the administration are the
creatures of the ruler. This autocratic trend is in accordance with a deep
political tradition in the Middle East, but it seems to be provoked above all
by a religious need-the need for an embodiment of the archetype or dynamic
image of the charismatic leader. Man wanted to feel that he was being guided
through the troubles of the world by a leader with supernatural gifts. The
difficulty, however, was that none of the leaders actually acclaimed as having
supernatural powers was much of a success politically. Even the Fatimid dynasty
in Egypt, though its rule lasted in all for over two centuries, produced no
politically impressive results.
In this
situation it is to be counted another of the achievements of the theologians
that the main body of Muslims rejected the Mutazilite view that the Quran was
created and instead asserted as a dogma that it was the very Word or Speech of
God and untreated. This is not mere hair-splitting, for it is a reinforcement
of the view that the Islamic community is divinely constituted, that is, that
it has been given a definite form of life by God. The Qur an, the basic
scripture of the community, contains the verbal description of this form of
life, and also expresses simply and concretely the value-beliefs that are
presupposed by this form of life and the associated and equally presupposed
views about the ultimate nature of reality. This point will concern us further
in the next section, for the Mutazilite doctrine of the createdness of the
Quran was the basis of the Mihna or Inquisition (833-849), which was an
important event in the relationships of the scholar-jurists to the rulers.
The
discussions about the Quran led on to widerranging discussions about the
attributes of God. In the Quran many epithets were given to
God, such as merciful, forgiving, knowing. The question was raised
whether God had attributes of mercy and knowledge which were somehow
distinct from his essence. Those who held that the Quran was uncreated tended
to say that it was the Speech of God, and that therefore God had an attribute
of speech which, though an integral part of him, was also in some way distinct.
Seven attributes came to be recognized as essential: life, knowledge
(omniscience), power (omnipotence), will, hearing, seeing, speech. The
Mutazilites, on the other hand, while bound to accept the Quranic epithets as
epithets, denied that God had any attributes distinct from his essence. Thus,
where he knew, he did so by his essence and not by a separate attribute of
knowledge. It is difficult for the modern student to understand what is at
stake here. Perhaps it is merely a defence of the supernatural character of the
Quran as the Speech of God by insisting that there are other attributes which
are also in some sense distinct from his essence. Perhaps it is also intended
to reinforce the belief that God is not a bare unity, as reason tends to
conceive him, but that God or ultimate reality has a determinate character
known by revelation; in this it would be implied that this understanding of
ultimate reality is constitutive of the community.
Parallel with the discussions about Gods attributes (and the
continuation of the debates on other questions at issue between the Mutazilites
and the Sunnites) there was a movement, among those who held the usual Sunnite
position, for the acceptance of rational methods of argument. The important
figure is al-Ashari (d. 935), who was trained as a Mu tazilite but in 912 at the
age of forty abandoned Mutazilism for the Sunnism of the Traditionist movement;
at the same time, however, he defended, by the methods of the Mu tazihtes, the
doctrines he had come to hold, and thus inaugurated one of the main schools of
Islamic theology, the Asharite. Another similar school was growing up in the
east about the same time, the Maturidite. A large section of the Traditionist
movement still held aloof and continued to avoid rational theology; and this
section eventually became almost identical with the adherents of the Hanbalite
legal rite, and may therefore conveniently be referred to as Hanbalites. The
formation of these theological schools (the Asharite and Maturidite) marks a
stage in the incorporation of the scientific worldview of the time into
Islamic thought. It was still only a partial incorporation, for it was largely
dependent on what had been assimilated by the Mutazilites in the time of
al-Mamun (813-833). After that period the scholar jurists had
probably little access to Greek thought, for it was studied almost solely by
non-Muslims or in little secluded coteries (as was seen in chapter III). So
what was achieved, though important, was far from complete.
In the period between al-Ashari and al-Ghazali the Asharite and Maturidite
schools of theology perfected their techniques (while remaining on the same
plane, as it were) and extended them to the whole field of theological
discussion. There were certain changes in emphasis, and some new points came to
the fore, such as the distinction between miracle and magic. It was only with
al-Ghazali, however, as we have seen, that the advances in philosophy since
al-Mamun were taken into account by a theologian, so that it became possible
for theology to rise to a higher technical plane. While this point about the
relation of theology to Greek thought is tolerably clear, it is not clear
whether the theologians had succeeded in maintaining a living relation between
theology and the contemporary historical and political situation, where the
caliph had lost most of his power and retained only a nominal suzerainty. At
the moment this question need only be suggested, since it is more appropriate
to discuss it later.
Among
minor achievements of the theologians in the period up to 9$o were the defence
of Islam against various non-Muslim groups within the borders of the state. The
Mutazilites are known as upholders of Islam against the Manichaeanism found in
the secretary class and elsewhere, and also against Jews and Christians. In the
case of the latter the aim seems to have been to stop ordinary Muslims from
arguing with the people of the Book. This was secured by the doctrine of the
corruption (tahrif) of the Jewish
and Christian scriptures -the Bible; but it is noteworthy that the doctrine was
never precisely formulated. In its amoeba-like changes of form it served its
end, for, if a Muslim found one form of the doctrine did not suit a particular
argument, he could always shift to another .6
As a
whole these achievements of the theologians may be described as the formulation
of dogma; and a little reflection on the course of thought just described will
lead to a better understanding of the place of dogma in the life of a society.
In many of the great disputes the question at issue was whether the life of
this great community was to be governed by Muhammads vision of the nature of
human life and of the universe in which it has to be lived, or by some other.
In their details, however, the struggles seem to be remote from this, and to be
waged round unimportant abstractions. What does it matter to a great empire,
one asks, whether the Quran is created or uncreated? The answer is
that this point in itself perhaps does not matter, but that something is
involved in it which does matter. A study of polemics, whether political,
religious or any other, shows that the points at which battle is joined are not
necessarily the most important, but those at which an attacking side thinks it
has advantageous ground or a defending side thinks it can yield no further
without suffering complete defeat.
In the particular case mentioned, those who objected to the
importance attached to the Quran (and the Traditions) in the life of the
community doubtless thought that, in asserting the Quran was created, they had
a good point. The Quran had manifestly appeared at a certain moment (or rather
series of moments) in time, and by insisting on this they no doubt hoped to
weaken the case of those who thought that Quranic principles should control
the life of the state. The other side, however, feeling strongly that the
Quran was the supernatural basis of the community (and knowing that for some
of them their material livelihood was bound up with the general acceptance of
this point), decided to stand firm here and to insist that the Quran as Gods
speech was uncreated. The question had all sorts of ramifications. The
opponents could reply, If you repeat the Quran, the sounds you make are not
eternal; if it is written, the paper and ink are not eternal. This objection
could be met by making further distinctions, and these would lead to further
questions. Eventually, however, one side gets the better of the argument. The
vast majority go to this side, and the other side is left as a dwindling
minority. The majority formulates succinctly the point for which they have been
fighting, and it becomes a dogma. A dogma is thus an assertion which after long
argument is accepted by the main body of the community and which is felt to
safeguard something essential to the well-being of the community.
Dogma is the record of an agreement. The community does not want to
repeat the argument, at least not for a long time. Theoretically the
possibility of reopening the question cannot be excluded, but in practice it is not contemplated. Indeed, one
might doubt whether Islam would remain Islam if it changed its mind about the
uncreatedness of the Quran. Thus the assertion about which agreement is
reached is given a special status, and comes to have a measure of fixity. This
fixity gives stability to the life of the community. Provided there has been
adequate discussion before the dogma has been formulated, and provided
political pressure has not been used to gain the acceptance of a formula not
sincerely accepted by the majority, this fixity is most valuable. The great
civilizations of the past have nearly always had the security that comes from a
relatively fixed and stable ideational basis.
On the other hand, fixity can be
bad if it prevents adjustment of the ideational basis of the community to
changing circumstances. Much of the bad odour attached to dogma at the
present time is due to the fact that our Western Christian dogmas have been too
rigid to be easily modified to meet the bewilderingly rapid changes in our
circumstances. It must be noticed here, however, that the failure to become
adapted to new situations may not be due to faults in the dogmas themselves,
for it is usually possible to effect some refinement in the conceptions. Most
often the difficulty is that the bearers of the dogmas feel that their
privileged status is being threatened and so are unwilling to make the
modifications. Whether something of this sort had happened to the Muslim
intellectuals before al-Ghazali is an important question that will have to be considered.
To consider, as has just been
done, the contemporary relevance of the ideas of the theologians is not in
itself sufficient. It is also necessary, for an understanding of al-Ghazalis
position, to look at the relations of the ruling institution or government to
the theologians, and more generally to the whole class of religious intellectuals.
Here again we stumble into a field which has not been much cultivated by
scholars; but from little patches here and there we obtain what we hope is a
reliable sample of the yield of the whole area.
During the Umayyad
period the class of religious intellectuals was only in process of formation.
In a few centres, such as Medina and Basra, devout men began to discuss
questions which presented themselves in the course of their practice of the
Islamic religion. At first, questions of conduct probably occupied most
attention, either the conduct of the rulers towards those whom they ruled or
the conduct of individual Muslims towards one another. Gradually some of these
questions were found to involve more strictly theological points; but even at
the end of the Umayyad period it could hardly be said that a systematic
theology had been formulated. The earliest theological views were those of
opponents of the government, Kharijites and Shiites, but in the course of
time theological positions were worked out, notably that of the Murjiites,
which would most naturally be associated with support of the Umayyad regime.
The body of men, mainly in Medina, who were interested in matters of conduct
and an Islamic way of life, are sometimes called the pious opposition because,
though not active opponents of the Umayyads, they disapproved of their Arab
rather than Islamic outlook. It further appears that this pious opposition
gave its general support to the movement which brought about the replacement of
the Umayyads by the `Abbasids, and that the `Abbasids in return gave some
recognition to the Islamic law which the devout scholars were in process of
elaborating. Among other things this recognition meant the appointment of
judges by the government from among the devout scholars?
This
understanding between the government and the religious intellectuals was in
keeping with the Persian political tradition which the `Abbasids followed to a
great extent. There was a Persian saying that religion and government are
twin-brothers,B and under the Sasanian empire the Zoroastrian clergy had
become almost a department of government. It is therefore not surprising that
soon after their coming to power in 750 the `Abbasids are found persecuting the
holders of religio-political views of which they disapproved. There was a
persecution of jindigs from about 779 to 786,9 and we hear of persons of Shiite
sympathies being imprisoned during the reign of ar-Rashid (786-8og).o Even
under the Umayyads there had been some use of force against religious
sectaries, but the main reason seems to have been political rather than
theological.,, For the `Abbasid persecutions just mentioned there may have been
political reasons; for example, many of those executed or imprisoned as
iin&gs belonged to the secretary class which was opposed to the growing
power of the Muslim religious intellectuals. Yet there was also a tendency to
regard a mans theological views, apart from any obvious political reference,
as a matter of which the government might properly take cognizance.
At this point it is pertinent to note that it is normal for a
government or ruler, whether autocratic or democratic, to support those views
(and the organized bodies of opinion holding them) which promise to gain the
greatest volume of support. The history of the Byzantine empire in the three or
four centuries after Constantine has numerous examples of attempts by the
ruling institution to get doctrinal compromises accepted which would
superficially unite opposing sectarian groups. This is a constant preoccupation
of rulers, and it constantly fails after a short period of trial. Serious
theological divergences spring from roots deep in a mans
constitution,
and, if a compromise does not satisfy the deep needs, men will sooner or later
turn from it. Theological compromises are worked out intellectually from
existing, partly contradictory, doctrinal formulations; but intellectual
operations of this kind take account only of what is explicit in the
formulations, whereas the formulations may be satisfactory only because of some
elements which are not explicit but implicit. If the compromise formula does
not make allowance for this implicit element, it will not satisfy those to whom
at a deep level the implicit element was important. Frequently the compromise
formula satisfies neither side.
These general considerations help one to understand a series of
events which mark an important stage in the relations between the religious
intellectuals and the government. The series of events is the Miltna or
Inquisition (833-849), during which government officials in certain important
centres were required to make public profession of their adherence to the
theological doctrine that the Quran was created. The opposing doctrine was
that the Quran was the untreated Speech of God. The government adopted this
policy on the advice of a group of theologians of the Mu`tazilite sect who had
become closely associated with it. Doubtless the government was attracted by
the doctrine because it looked the kind of doctrine which would bring harmony
between opposing political factions-between the constitutionalist bloc with the
Islamic intellectuals on the one hand and the autocratic bloc with the
secretaries on the other hand. The Mu tazilites themselves were presumably
looking for a way of reconciling the conflicting claims of reason and
revelation--a genuine problem of the times with important practical
consequences. But they did not go far enough to satisfy the deep inner demand
of the Shiites for a charismatic leader, and at the same time their concession
to the Shiites in depreciating the place of the Quran alarmed those whose deep
need was to belong to a charismatic community, since in denying that the Quran
was the eternal Speech of God they seemed to be denying that the community was
divinely instituted.
In the
course of the Inquisition most of the intellectuals who were required to make
public profession of the doctrine did so, whatever their real views. A few
refused, and of these some were put to death. The most important recusant was
Ahmad ibn-Hanbal (d. 855) who suffered in various ways but was not executed.
Perhaps the authorities were aware of the great admiration for him among the
populace of Baghdad. To later generations his successful passive resistance
made him a hero, and it may be because of this, as much as because of his
eminence as a jurist, that one of the four great Sunnite legal rites came to
bear his name. Yet his example, though it showed that deeply-held conviction
could not be changed by force, did not make his followers ready at all times to
stand up for their convictions against government pressure. On the contrary,
though they may occasionally have boldly maintained their convictions, the
chief impression they give is that they were men anxious to gain government
support. They also showed themselves quite unscrupulous in using the physical
violence of mobs against their theological opponents.2
On the
long-term view the chief result of the Inquisition was to make it clear that
the government or ruling institution was stronger than the scholar-jurists. For
some time before this it had been the instinct of the more sensitive members of
this class or their predecessors to refuse all government appointments and all
gifts from the caliphs; some were prepared to act as judges but without any
financial emoluments. The wisdom of such an attitude was now apparent. So many
of the scholar
jurists must now have been
financially dependent on the ruling institution that they were unable as a body
to resist pressure from it. Its abandonment of the policy of the Inquisition
was therefore presumably not due to Ahmad ibn-Hanbal and the Baghdad mob, but
to the failure of the policy to win a sufficient volume of Shiite support. The
change of policy meant the end of the political power of the Mu tazilites and
the beginning of their decline. When about 912 al-Ashari left them and began to
use their methods of argument to defend an essentially Hanbalite position, they
ceased to be a significant factor in the theological life of the Islamic world,
though they continued to exist for centuries. They may at times have suffered,
along with certain philosophical coteries, from the disapproval of the
government.13
A
glimpse of the state of affairs about 922 is provided by Louis Massignons
study of the trial of al-Hallaj.4 The political background of this trial was
the political struggle for the position of vizier, which was mainly a struggle
between two families, that of Ibn-al-Furat (855-924) and `Ali ibn-`Isa
(859-945). Massignon describes the former as tending to an absolutist
position and having moderate Shiite sympathies and the latter as being
constitutional and broadly Sunnite; that is to say, they represented what
were called above the autocratic and constitutionalist blocs. It is further
clear from Massignons study that the gadis or judges are mixed up in the
politics of the time. Indeed the family of `Ali ibn-`Isa is one of
scholar-jurists or religious intellectuals which has made its way into the
class of secretaries or administrators. His grandfather, Da rid ibn `Ali (d. 884), was the founder
of the Zahirite legal rite, while an uncle, Muhammad ibn-Daud (d. 910), was
vizier for a day in 908. Numerous details show that the religious intellectuals
are now powerless against the vizier. It is their right to give legal opinions (fataws), but the vizier can choose
between conflicting opinions -and did so in respect of the condemnation of
al-Hallaj. One scholar-jurist, Ibn- Ata, a follower of al-Hallaj, who made a public statement approving
of the latters creed, was roughly handled at the bidding of the vizier and
beaten on the head with his own shoes until blood ran down his nostrils;
whether as a consequence of this or not, he died a few days later.
Careful
study of the condemnation of al-Hallaj seems to show that this was essentially
a political decision. Muhammad ibn-D5-ad was the author of a work which was
composed round an anthology of poems, and of which the first half dealt with
platonic love; this conception was absolutely opposed to the teaching of
al-Hallaj about love for God. i 5
When the case of al-Hallaj was judicially considered during the first vizierate
of Ibn-al-Furat (about gog), Muhammad ibn-Da ud, as head of the Zahirite legal
rite in succession to his father, gave a legal opinion (fatwa) condemning the doctrines of al-Hallaj. Behind this legal
opinion, however, there was the hostility of Imamite Shiite party and their
leader, Abu-Sahl an-Nawbakhti. In the course of his preaching al-Hallaj had
tried to present his views to the Imamites as a development of their own.
Probably many of the rank and file were attracted to him. Perhaps AbuSahl,
with the scepticism and the discernment of an old politician, had for a time
thought he might prove a useful instrument. Eventually, however, Abu-Sahl and
the other Imamite leaders became bitterly hostile to him. He acquired followers
among the leading administrators, and gained a foothold at court, where the
caliph had already shown Shiite sympathies. The Imamites must have been
seriously alarmed at the growth of this essentially Sunnite form of mysticism;
its teaching that any man might rise to sanctity and obtain supernatural
charismata cut the root from their doctrine that charis
mata were a special privilege
of the`Alid line. The Imamites, however, were unable to act directly against
alHallaj, since no Imamite jurist had any official authority and there was no
subservient police force; and it is therefore remarkable that they were able to
obtain Sunnite legal opinions condemning him. 16 The ultimate source
of the condemnation of al-Hallaj is thus the political danger to the Imamite
party, the centre of the autocratic bloc; but what made it practicable was
the political weakness of the Sunnite jurists and their readiness, where no
clear principle was at stake, to please the ruling institution.
By 945
there had been an important change in the political situation. The caliph had
lost most of his power and no longer appointed viziers who actually ruled. In
Baghdad the supreme authority was in the hands of a family of Persian
(Daylamite) war-lords, the Buwayhids (or Buyids), who had the title of supreme
commander (amir al-umara).17
The Buwayhids were Shiites and represented the autocratic bloc, but they
were not able to make the territories they ruled completely Shiite, perhaps
mainly because of the strong hold of Sunnism on the ordinary people. The
Sunnite scholar-jurists retained most of their influence in the restricted
field of law, but Shiite jurists were officially recognized along with them.
Unfortunately this aspect of the Buwayhid period has not been fully studied,
and it is impossible to go into further detail about it. 18
While
the Buwayhids still retained control of Baghdad a powerful state was being
created in eastern Persia, Afghanistan and India by a war-lord of Turkish
descent, Mahmud of Ghazna (regnabat
998-1030). One or two small incidents are recorded which may be taken as
straws. At one point he summoned the Ash`arite theologian Ibn-Furak (d. 1015)
to Ghazna to reply to a charge of doctrinal error (in holding that Muhammads
prophethood did not continue after his death).19 On another
occasion, after a drive against the Batinites in Rayy, Mahmud appointed a
reliable Sunnite scholar, Abu-Hatim ibn-Khamush, as a kind of censor to examine the theological opinions of newcomers
who wanted to settle in the town, before they were allowed to give public
addresses.20 This marks a turning of the tide again towards Sunnism, and the
beginning of the support of Turkish rulers for it.
The
resurgence of Sunnism in Baghdad and the lands dependent on it began about 1000
as Buwayhid power declined, and entered a new and decisive phase in ro5 5 when
another dynasty of Turkish war-lords, the Seljuqs, gained control of Baghdad.
At first, the influence of the Hanbalites was strongest, and under Tughril
Begs vizier, al-Kunduri, curses against the Asharites were added to those
against the Rafidites (Imamite Shiites) in the Friday prayers.2 The accession
to the throne (the emirate) of Alp-Arslan in 1063 led to a change of policy. In
his previous provincial governorship he had had as vizier the great
Nizam-al-Mulk, and the latter now became vizier of the whole empire and
remained so, with increasing power, until his death in toga. Nizamal-Mulk at
once had the cursing of the Asharites stopped, and began to implement a policy
of supporting and strengthening the Asharites against the other theological
and legal schools. Towards the end of 1065 he began to build a college at
Baghdad, which was opened in September 1067, and is known as the Nizamiyya.
This is the college to which al-Ghazali went as professor in rog1. Similar
colleges were also founded in other important cities of the empire. Thus
Asharite theology became the form of Islamic doctrine supported by the
government.
Details
have been preserved of the personal aspects of some of the theological disputes
of the time, and these throw some light on the general conditions. In 1058 the
wealthy and learned Traditionist al-Khatib al-Baghdadi had to leave the city
because of the difficulties made for him by the Hanbalites.22 The opening of
the Nizamiyya college in 1067 was the signal for fresh activity by the
Hanbalites against both the Asharites and the Mutazilites, whom they regarded
as equally dangerous, since both practised kalam
or rational theology. When in 1068 there was some question of the leading
Mu tazilite Abu-Ali ibn-al-Walid lecturing at the Nizamiyya, one of the
Hanbalite leaders, the Sharif Abufar al-Hashimi, organized a demonstration of
protest which seems to have gained its end.23 About the same time it came to
light that one of the most promising young Hanbalites, Ibn--Agil,had been
receiving instruction from Mutazilites, and a serious view was taken of this by
some of the leaders, notably the same Abu-Ja far al-Hashimi. The matter
aroused much public interest, and led to disturbances and minor riots, while
Ibn-Agil had to lie low. The pressure on him was such that eventually in 1072
he made a retractation which satisfied the Sharif Abu-Jafar. There has recently
been discovered and published the autograph diary of one of the lesser
Hanbalites, with numerous entries covering about a year from 1068 to 1068; and
this suggests that the Hanbalites were not so solidly against Ibn-`Agil as had
previously been thought, and that the pressure on him was not due to an
official decision of the whole Hanbalite body but was mainly from the
SharifAbu-Jafar and his friends among the Hanbalites.24
Another
series of incidents began with the visit to the Nizamiyya in 1067 of the
Asharite preacher, Abu-Nasr al-Qushayri (son of the well-known mystic
Abu-lQasim al-Qushayri). The Hanbalites stirred up riots in which twenty
persons were killed. Once again the Sharif Abu-Jafar took a leading part in the
attack, perhaps with some encouragement from his cousin, the caliph al-Muqtadi.
The attacks were not confined to the preacher who was the original cause of the
trouble, but included the senior professor at the Nizamiyya, AbuIs haq
ash-Shirazi. It is significant that the latter wrote to complain to
Nizam-al-Mulk himself and to obtain his backing. The vizier did his best to
calm down the affair. He wrote pointing out how al-Ashari himself had shown
great respect for Ahmad ibn-Hanbal, and at the same time (perhaps at the
request of the caliph) he summoned Abu-Nasr al-Qushayri back to Khurasan-in any
case the visit to Baghdad had been incidental to making the pilgrimage, but the
scholars of the period were mobile, and he might have remained in Baghdad but
for the
storm.23
These
details help to give some idea of conditions in Baghdad in the latter half of the
eleventh century. Most prominent is the rivalry between the Hanbalites and the
Asharites, which is in no way reduced by the official support given to both
sides. It is also clear that an important section of the populace of Baghdad is
behind the Hanbalites and is ready to stage a riot when given any
encouragement. At the same time there are traces of serious differences within
the Hanbalites. In general the policy of Nizam-al-Mulk, as of all rulers, is to
remove disharmonies as far as possible; but, though his backing of the
Asharites was not unconditional, it doubtless added to the truculence of the
Hanbalites. Apparently both parties concentrated their attention on maintaining
and improving their position in Baghdad.
No one
can read through, or even rapidly peruse, the opening book of al-Ghazalis Revival of the Religious Sciences without
being struck by the bitterness of his criticisms of the scholar-jurists
(including theologians) of his time. The first of the forty books of this
lengthy work is entitled Knowledge (or
Science), for which the Arabic is `ilm; and the corresponding agent-noun
is `dlim, with the plural `ulama (often anglicized as ulema),
which properly means knower or scientist but is here usually translated as
scholar-jurist. An understanding of these etymological connections helps one
to realize the appropriateness of a critique of scholar jurists in a book
dealing with Knowledge.
This critique of the scholar-jurists is by no means a novel or
original feature in the thought of al-Ghazali. From the beginning the ascetic
and mystical movement in Islam had made vigorous criticisms of the worldliness
of the rulers of the Islamic empire and of those scholars who were prepared to
take office (in such positions as judges) under the rulers. Under the Umayyad
regime, while the class of religious intellectuals was still in embryo and they
scarcely deserved to be called scholar jurists, a member of this group might
act as judge temporarily on behalf of the caliph or a provincial governor, but
he often did so without receiving any remuneration; this was presumably
possible because he was still receiving a stipend from the state like all the
other Muslims. The recognition given to the scholar jurists at the beginning of
the `Abbasid period (7go onwards), together with the apparent disappearance of
the system of stipends, led to a new situation. The appointment of a
scholar-jurist to a judgeship became a more frequent occurrence, but at the
same time fewer of the scholar-jurists could afford to fulfil such duties without remuneration. A new Islamic educational
system developed, directed to the study of the religious sciences and
particularly of Islamic law; and those who were trained in this way normally
expected a career in some branch of public service, or the administration of
the empire. It was impossible, however, to be involved in the work of
government without being infected by the worldliness, the love of wealth, power
and honour, which was endemic in the ruling institution of a great empire.
Along
with this more or less inevitable trend towards worldliness among those trained
in the religious sciences there went a movement of protest. Some idea of its
volume may be gained from the numerous quotations given by al-Ghazali in the
sixth chapter of the book mentioned.26 These include sayings of the
Companions of Muhammad, such as the caliph Umar. The earlier sayings, however,
unless they are of a very general nature, are suspect as later inventions. A
relatively early ascetic, al-Fudayl ibn- Iyad (d. 803), is reported to have
said that wicked scholars will be dealt with first on the Resurrection Day,
even before the idol-worshippers: and this may well be genuine. From other
sources we learn how he boldly criticized and upbraided Haran arRashid to his
face; and a remark of his about avoiding Quran-reciters since their evidence
would be accepted against one seems to imply his awareness of the consequences
of a measure of public recognition of this minor section of the religious
institution.Z7 Somewhat later Yahyaibn-Mu`adhar-Razi (d. 871) complained
that the glory of science and wisdom departs when they are used to gain this
world, and taunted the men of science with having castles like Caesars,
mansions like Chosroes, . . . doctrines like Satans, and no place for
Muhammads law.x8 Another bold ascetic, Hatim the Deaf (d. 851), publicly shamed the judge of Rayy (Rey, in Persia) in his own
audience-chamber because of the ostentatious luxury in which he lived.29
Criticisms of worldly and hypocritical scholars are to be found in the extant
works of men like al-Harith ibn-Asad al-Muhasibi (d. 857) and Abu-Talib
al-Makki (d. 996).30
In view
of all this it might he thought that al-Ghazali was merely repeating customary
criticisms. The vehemence of his expressions, however, leads one to think that
this was something about which he had strong personal feelings; and this
impression is confirmed by the fact that he devotes most of the preface of The Revival of the Religious Sciences to
commenting on the shortcomings of contemporary scientists, that is, the
scholar-jurists. He addresses this preface to one who is inclined to blame
those like himself who for reasons of piety turn from worldliness and from the
worldly scholars (of the religious sciences) who, according to Tradition, would
be the persons most severely punished on Resurrection Day. Then he continues:
Indeed, there is no cause for
your persistence in pride apart from the disease, common to the multitudes of
ordinary men, of failing to notice the essence of this matter and not realizing
how important and serious it is. The world-to-come is advancing and this-world
receding; the time (of death) is near, the journey long, the provisions deficient,
the danger great and the road blocked. Everything save knowledge and action
sincerely for the sake of God by a clear-sighted critic (of himself) is
rejected. To travel the road of the world-tocome without guide or companion,
when its mischances are so many, is wearisome and laborious. The guides for the
way are the ulema, who are the heirs of the prophets. But this age is bereft of
them; there remain only those who are such in outward seeming; over most of
them Satan has gained mastery. Their, rebellious nature has deceived them. Each
has become greatly delirious of his present transient lot. He has come to
consider good evil and evil good, so that religious knowledge has been
obliterated and the light of guidance in various parts of the world quenched. They
have led men to suppose that there is no knowledge (or science) except a legal-opinion (fatwa) of the government
by which the judges are helped to settle a quarrel of the plebeian masses; or
else argument, by which the seeker of
glory is armed for knock-out victory;
or else meretricious saj` (ornate
rhymed prose), by which the preacher deceives the ordinary people. Apart from
these three things there is no snare to hunt forbidden (pleasures) and no net
to catch worldly vanities.
The
science of the road of the world-to-come, on the other hand, and the learning,
wisdom, knowledge, illumination, light, guidance and direction, as God calls
them in scripture, by which the noble Muslims of old lived their lives, have
become rejected among men and completely forgotten. Since this is a grave
weakness in a religion and a black mark against it, I thought it right to busy
myself with composing this book, out of a concern for the revival of the
religious sciences, to show the practices of the former leaders, and to make
clear the limits of the useful sciences in the eyes of the prophets and the
noble Muslims of old. 31
Throughout
the book of Knowledge al-Ghazali
never allows the readers to forget his critical attitude towards the
scholar-jurists of the day. His discussion of the various branches of
religious knowledge (in chapter z) culminates in an assessment of them by the
criterion of how far they help to fit a man for the life of the worldto-come.
The same conception becomes a basis (in the following chapter) for deciding how
far it is good to pursue any particular branch; while the long sixth chapter
points the contrast between the ulema of thisworld and the ulema of the
world-to-come. The following are the
chief points made by al-Ghazali.
(I)
Most of the religious knowledge of the day, as studied by the scholar-jurists,
is purely this-worldly and deals only with such matters as the ordering of the
life of society. From what al-Ghazali says, it appears that they were in the
habit of spending much time and energy in the discussion of legal points which
had little practical application; for example, details for formulae of divorce
which were perhaps rarely used, or questions concerning fine points of
difference between the recognized legal rites. (It should be noted, however,
that in respect of such matters our general knowledge of the period is scanty
and does not enable us to do more than make deductions from al-Ghazalis own
words.) While those who claim to be religious scholars thus exercise themselves
in academic trifles, they neglect the real business of religion, the
preparation of man for the life of the world-to-come. Those who are so learned
about rare forms of divorce can tell you nothing about the simpler things of
the spiritual life, such as the meaning of sincerity towards God or trust in
him (ikhlas, tawakkul).
(2) The
attempt of such men to justify their conduct on religious grounds is
unsatisfactory. They say that this is a communal obligation (fard kifaya), that is, something which
ought to be done by some unspecified members of the community for the sake of
the whole, but which is not incumbent on every one as is an individual
obligation (fard `ayn). But al-Ghazali points out that it is not
for a Muslim to undertake a communal obligation until he has performed all
his individual obligations, and that too many persons are performing this
communal obligation while certain other communal obligations, such as being
a doctor in a small town, are neglected-there are many towns where the only doctors
are Jews and Christians, persons not qualified to give evidence in a Muslim
law-court. So al-Ghazali concludes that it is not zeal for the performance of
communal obligations that leads so many to become scholar-jurists.
(3) The
corollary of this is that in fact the majority of the religious scholars of the
day are chiefly concerned with their professional qualifications as a means of
gaining wealth, power and position. This is really the heart of his critique.
The intellectuals of the age have become infected by the worldliness of the
rulers. This is a worse fault, however, in those who claim to be religious
scholars, for it means that they are hypocritical and do not practise what they
preach. Among al-Ghazalis quotations is one from a poet not named which echoes
the Gospel saying about the salt which has lost its savour: 0 reciters (of the
Quran), 0 salt of the city, what use is salt, if the salt is corrupted?32
(4)
Al-Ghazali further holds that the true scholar will have nothing to do with
rulers and will not accept offices from them. The true scholar will even avoid
having to give a formal legal-opinion when he is asked to do so-presumably
because this was part of the official legal procedure and indeed of the
business of government.33 He even held that the religious scholar
should teach freely without any remuneration.34
(5) While al-Ghazali has this generally critical attitude, he does
not entirely condemn the study of the various branches of religious knowledge.
They have their uses, even if these are restricted to the ordering of society
in this world. What is important is not to forget
that mans true destiny is in the world-to-come, and, in the light of this,
to allow the usefulness of each branch of religious knowledge to determine the
extent to which it is studied.
A
further criticism of the religious intellectuals of the time is implicit in
another work by al-Ghazali, The Decisive
Criterion for distinguishing between Islam and Unbelief, which was composed some time
after The Revival of the Religious
Sciences. It was apparently the custom for various schools of thought among
the theologians to regard as an unbeliever anyone who disagreed with them on
some comparatively minor point. Al-Ghazali complains that men are being too
light-hearted in calling other Muslims unbelievers, since this is an assertion
with serious legal consequences-it is not a crime to kill an unbeliever. Part
of the trouble is that, if one defines unbelief as regarding Muhammad as
false in any part of his message, then each party can show how the others
regard as false some parts of what it considers to be the message. This leads
to a discussion of interpretation and five different senses of existence.
From this standpoint the disputes between sects such as those mentioned are
seen to be about canons of interpretation. Al-Ghazali proposes the eirenic
solution that, so long as a man accepts the basic credal statements in some sense he cannot be called an
unbeliever, but at most erring or heretical.
It has
also to be noticed that, especially during the period of his professorship at
Baghdad from July 1091 to November 1095, al-Ghazali was deeply involved both in
the worldliness of the intellectuals and in the dependence on the government
which he later criticized. The teacher to whom he owed most, al-Juwayni, had
himself been appointed by the vizier, Nizam-al-Mulk, to the latters new
college at Nishapur, as part of his policy of encouraging and supporting
Asharite theologians. On al-Juwaynis death in July 1085 al-Ghazali had gone
to the camp of the vizier, and had apparently spent the following six years
in his entourage. It was Nizam-al-Mulk who was responsible for his appointment
to the professorship in Baghdad. In Baghdad he was at the official ceremony of
taking the oath to the new caliph, al-Mustazhir, in February 1094, and was
sufficiently well known to him to be asked by him to write a polemical work
against the Batinites. Thus al-Ghazali had known something of the favour of
rulers. It may also be that after the deaths of Nizam-al-Mulk and the sultan
Malikshah in the autumn of 1092 he found relations with the rulers difficult.
There was fighting between members of the Seljuq family, and it was not till
about February 1095 that Barkiyaruq was finally recognized in Baghdad. The
caliph and al-Ghazali had shown some support for other candidates for supreme
power, and al-Ghazali would therefore be suspect to the government after
February 1095.
During
this period he must also have known something of the fierce rivalries between
the scholar-jurists of Baghdad, especially between the Hanbalites and the
Ash`arites. The Hanbalites seem to have been still furious at the very existence of the Nizamiyya college and at
everyone connected with it. Even between the professors there personal
difficulties seem to have been considerable. One of the men whom al-Ghazali
seems to have replaced had been appointed only the year before, but was brought
back after al-Ghazalis departure. Politics doubtless entered into the appointment
and demotion of professors in ways which have not been properly studied, and
for the study of which adequate materials may not be available.
For
men in such circumstances their whole careers would depend on worldly
calculations of political advantage and disadvantage. It would be difficult for
them to be immersed in such a life and not to accept in full the values of this
section of society. Thus personal experience of this kind of life is a large
part of the ground for al-Ghazalis criticism of the scholar-jurists.
Similarly, his advice to have nothing to do with rulers must be the outcome of
some deep disillusionment with governmental support.
4 DOGMATIC THEOLOGY FROM A NEW STANDPOINT
(a)
General Attitude to Theology
After
the study of the Quran, at first mainly by memorizing, the staple of higher
education-education in the Islamic sciences-was jurisprudence with its
subordinate disciplines, such as the study of Traditions and traditionists.
Theology or kalam was like a special
subject, somewhat beyond the usual curriculum, to which only a few outstanding
students would give prolonged attention. Of all the men named as being teachers
of al-Ghazali only al-Juwayni seems to have lectured to him in theology. This
must have been in the years immediately preceding the death of al-Juwayni in
1085. It is unlikely that after this al-Ghazali met anyone who influenced his
theological development, except negatively by stating views which he felt bound
to criticize.
Chronologically
these well-attested facts fit in with the account al-Ghazali gives in Deliverance from Error, except for the
fact that he speaks of having written some books about theology, whereas his
extant theological works, notably one which may be called The Golden Mean in Belief, are clearly subsequent to
his study of philosophy (as will presently be explained in detail). It is
possible that, when he wrote this, al-Ghazali was thinking about books on the
principles of jurisprudence. On other grounds, however, it seems certain that Deliverance from Error is arranged
schematically and does not follow the strict chronological order. When this is
admitted, there is no further difficulty about the relation of the
autobiographical statements to the extant works. There is an important
consequence, however, namely that we have no information about al-Ghazalis
theological views until after he had studied philosophy and was well on the way
to becoming a Sufi. The major extant work is the book just mentioned, The Golden Mean in Belief, and it cannot
have been written earlier than the summer of 1095, just before he left Baghdad.
It quotes The Inconsistency of the
Philosophers (completed in January 1095) and other books of about the
same time; its use of syllogisms shows that it is subsequent to his study of
Aristotelian logic; and the impression of a careful scholar like Maurice
Bouyges was that the writers preoccupations were the same as in the Inconsistency.3S On the other hand, The Golden Mean is prior to the Revival, since it is mentioned there.
Now
we know something about al-Ghazalis later attitude to theology from what he
says about it in Deliverance from Error. 36 There
he makes two main points. Firstly, the aim of the theologians was to defend
dogma against heretical aberrations and innovations. Secondly, the theologians
failed to meet the logical demands of those who had studied Aristotelian logic,
since their arguments were directed against those who already shared their own
point of view to a considerable extent. He had already spoken of this limited aim
of theology in the Revival, while
also emphasizing that theology contributed nothing to the actual practice of
the religious life.37 That he felt something of this inadequacy of theology as
he wrote The Golden Mean is suggested
by the prayer at the end: We pray God that he will not make this of ill
outcome for us, but will place it in the balance of good deeds when our acts
are given back to us.39 Nevertheless the references to it in the Revival and other later works show that
he continued to regard it as valuable so far as it went. In a short summary of
the Revival he has an interesting
description of it. He is speaking of three possible attitudes towards the
doctrines of the creed: firstly, belief or simple acceptance, then knowledge of
their proofs and finally knowledge of their mysteries. After mentioning the
statement of the creed in the Revival, he
goes on: as for the proofs ... we have set them down in The Golden Mean in Belief in some hundred pages; it is a book
devoted entirely to this main matter (?), containing the essence of the science
of the theologians, but more adequate in its proofs and more apt to knock at
the doors of knowledge (of the mysteries) than the official (or normal)
theology which is met in the books of the theologians.39
The
conclusion to which these reflections lead is that the statements in Deliverance from Error about rejecting
theology and turning from it have to be understood in a restricted sense.
Al-Ghazali was dissatisfied with theology because it contributed little or
nothing to the attainment of that goal of the individual life which he
described as salvation or the bliss of Paradise. But he thought that it had a
prophylactic function in the life of the community, and, in so far as this was
so, he continued to hold the views of the Ash` ante school to which he had
always belonged. There is no evidence in the works generally accepted as
authentic that in his closing years he abandoned Ash`arite doctrines for the
Neoplatonism he had refuted in The
Inconsistency of the Philosophers. On the contrary, the date which has been
found for a small work called The
Restraining of the Commonalty from the Science of Theology sets the
completion of this work only a few days before his death. There seem to be no
strong grounds for not accepting this date. The book implies that the theology
which ordinary men are to be kept away from is Sunnite theology, and might be
looked on as an elaboration of a point of view already expressed in The Golden Mean.4° In other words,
although al-Ghazali thought the importance of theology had been. greatly
exaggerated, he continued to take up a theological position which was broadly
Asharite.
(b) .4l-Ghaialis Exposition of His
Theological Views
In studying al-Ghazalis
dogmatic theology the chief interest is in noticing the contrast between his
exposition and that of al-Juwayni. For this purpose we have, by al-Juwayni, The Right Guidanre,41 a work
of about twice the length of al-Ghazalis Golden
Mean and covering much the same ground-both works are of what has been
called the Summa Theologica type. In addition we have The N4dmian Creed, 42 which covers most of the subjects
of The Golden Mean in about half the
compass. According to the manuscript, however, this book is the version of a
young Spanish scholar who had it from al-Ghazali in Baghdad, presumably between
1093 and 1095. This would mean that this was the book which al-Ghazali used as
a text for his lectures; in the main it must be al-Juwaynis book, but
al-Ghazali may have made slight modifications here and there 43
Proceeding on the assumption that it is essentially the work of al-Juwayni, we
note that it stands somewhere between The
Right Guidance and The Golden Mean; the
author has become interested in some of the problems raised by the philosophers,
but he does not deal with philosophical objections nearly so fully as
al-Ghazali. This confirms the reports that al-Juwayni introduced al-Ghazali to
the study of philosophy.44
In his
own exposition al-Ghazali follows the standard plan for the arrangement of
topics in such treatises 45 He has four parts or chapters dealing
respectively with the proof of the existence of a Creator, the attributes of
God, the relations of God and man, and questions connected with prophethood and
the imamate (or leadership of the Islamic community). In addition he has four
prefaces, in the fourth of which he briefly explains the nature of syllogism.
The early pages dealing with
the proof of the existence of God are sufficient to show how completely
al-Ghazali had accepted the syllogism as the primary form of argument. Thus his
essential proof of the existence of God is:
Every
originated thing has a cause. The world is an originated thing. Therefore the
world has a cause.
He then
considers how we know the two premisses. The major premiss he regards as a
necessary first principle. The minor premiss he proves by another syllogism:
Everything
not-without-originated-things is originated.
Every
body is not-without-originated-things. Therefore every body is originated.
He then
points out that the dispute with the philosophers is over the major premiss
here, and proceeds to discuss it further. All this is in sharp contrast with
al-Juwaynis basic argument: an originated-thing may exist or not exist;
therefore it requires a determinant, to determine whether it is to exist or not
exist at a particular time. This determinant may be either a cause (`illa), or a nature (tabita) or a conscious
agent; various arguments show that it is not a cause or a nature; therefore it
must be a conscious agent. This method of enumerating possibilities
exhaustively and then eliminating all but one was very popular with
al-Ghazalis predecessors, and al-Juwayni was still attached to it. On a minor
point he has what is tantamount to a syllogism:
What
does not precede originated-things is originated.
Substances
do not precede accidents (which are originated).
Therefore
the world (the totality of substances and accidents) is originated.
Al-Juwayni, however, does not
call attention to the special form of this argument. If, as is possible, he had
some elementary knowledge of syllogistic logic, he did not realize its
superiority to the methods of argument traditional among Islamic theologians.4b
The
importance of the syllogism was not so much in respect of particular arguments
as of the system as a whole. There is a certain order in syllogistic reasoning.
The premiss of one syllogism may be the conclusion of another, and this other
is then logically prior. If the order of priority is not duly observed, there
is a vicious circle in the reasoning. While there could be chains of reasoning
according to the older logic, there was not the same over-all order. Each chain
of argument tends to be treated as an isolated unit, and propositions are
asserted without considering whether they are logically prior or posterior to
others. Al-Juwayni has a section proving that God is not a body, directed
mainly against Muslim anthropomorphists; and he then follows it with one on
substance directed mainly against the Christians. Al-Ghazali changes this
order; he first proves that God is not a substance (or atom), and then neatly
adds that he cannot be a body, since a body is two or more substances A7 In
particular, attention may be directed to a remark by al-Juwayni that if you
call God a body, you either contradict the proof of the originatedness of
substances, since this proof is based on their being receptive of composition,
contiguity and separation, or ... In a syllogistic system the point could have
been made more vigorously, since there could have been a reference to a
proposition already proved; here, because of the lack of a recognized order,
there is some suggestion of uncertainty about previous conclusions. When in Deliverance from Error al-Ghazali notes
that the philosophers do not manage to prove all their metaphysical views
syllogistically, this is an indication of his intense interest in logic and of
the attention he paid to the logical aspects of others thought and his own.
This concern for logical method and logical order leads to many changes in the
detail of his proofs, compared with those of al-Juwayni.
The
other point to be commented on is al-Ghazalis much greater awareness of the
philosophers as opponents, and a corresponding reduction of emphasis on arguments
against other adversaries. In The Right
Guidance al-Juwayni makes practically no attempt to argue against the
Neoplatonic philosophers. In The Nilamian
Creed the philosophical conceptions of the necessary, the possible and the
impossible are in the forefront, and a measure of attention is given to the
positions of the philosophers. But al-Ghazalis study of philosophy had brought
into his ken a whole new world of objections, and this is apparent in his
exposition of theology, especially in the proofs of the existence of God 48
These
two points-the conscious basing of the arguments on syllogistic logic, and the
attention to objections from a Neoplatonic standpoint-are in fact al-Ghazalis
great contributions to the later development of Islamic theology. From now
onwards all the rational theologians in Islam wrote in a way which assumed a
philosophical outlook in pre-theological matters, and often explicitly
discussed such matters. Indeed in some of the treatises the philosophical
preliminaries occupy by far the larger part of the work, so that the impression
is given that the authors were more interested in the philosophy than in the
actual theology.
From
another point of view it might be asserted that what al-Ghazali had done was to
effect a complete fusion of the Greek and Islamic intellectual traditions. This
refers, of course, to the Greek tradition in the form in which it was still
alive in the lands of the `Abbasid caliphate. While there is much truth in the
assertion, it must not be allowed to make us think that the philosophers were
essentially an alien element in the population and that al-Ghazali made their
disciplines available for native thinkers. There was much that was common to
the philosophers and the theologians. Both believed in rational argument. The
difference was that the philosophers had elaborated logic more fully and were
more conscious of what they were doing. The theologians, however, had also
given some thought to logic, though perhaps more in the sphere of jurisprudence
than of theology proper (but all theologians were also competent in
jurisprudence). Thus it would be wrong to say that more up-to-date or more
scientific methods were incorporated into theology, for thus we should be
importing our own values. Both sides had the same values, but the philosophers
had realized them more fully.
The
real opposition, at least in Baghdad, was the Hanbalite school of theology,
which was still suspicious of rational argument in any form, and continued to
be so. The most remarkable expression of this line of thought is in The Refutation of the Logicians by Ibn
Taymiyya (d. 1328). What is remarkable is that, though the author finds
weaknesses in Aristotelian logic with great skill and acumen, he does not use
his obvious mastery of the subject to provide a superior logic, but to urge the
abandonment altogether of the attempt to systematize the material of revelation
(in the Quran and the Traditions) and to defend it rationally. This distrust
of reason is an important trend to be found in Western civilization as well as
in Islam. It is still alive in Islam in the Wahhabites of Arabia and other
fundamentalists. In the West the protest against excessive rationalism has
been taken up by
existentialism, and this is perhaps the nearest man can come to the statement
of a rational case for distrusting reason.
The
new perspective introduced by al-Ghazali into Islamic theology, then, became
part of its permanent nature. In this we see one important aspect of the growth
of a theology. The theologian at any given time is producing replies to the
objections raised by the opponents of his religion. These opponents attack him
at every possible point. Some of their criticisms will be stronger than others;
some of his replies will be more effective than others. All this he hands on to
his successor, who is usually his pupil. Where the replies have been effective,
the pupil repeats them; if he can think of better ones he substitutes them; and
he has also to add new replies to new criticisms. Thus the theology of a
religious community is constantly growing. It retains all that is satisfactory
in the work of past theologians. There may be less emphasis on old arguments,
since the bearers of the criticisms to which they were replies may have died
out-but there is always the chance that someone may revive an old objection, or
that it may crop up in a new form. So in its intellectual basis a religious
community retains something of all its past-of its responses to the varying
situations through which it defined itself. There is even a sense in which the
continued existence of different intellectual traditions within a community
(such as fundamentalist and rational-theological) is part of its definition of
itself. From this standpoint we begin to realize the vastness of al-Ghazalis
contribution to present-day Islam.
VI
THE BITTERNESS OF WORLDLY SUCCESS
INTRODUCTORY NOTE
In the course of the year rags
al-Ghazali had what would now be called a breakdown. Although it was
essentially a psychological or spiritual crisis, it came to a head in July of
that year when physical symptomsan inability to utter words-forced him to
abandon lecturing. Since some of his books must be ascribed to about this date,
it is probable that he was able to continue writing. After
much hesitation he at length came to a decision. In November 1095 he set out
from Baghdad and made for Syria, thereby abandoning his professorship and his
position as a public figure in order to lead what was in effect a monastic
life., In order to understand this astonishing step, we must look at
the previous history of the sufior mystical-monastic movement?
I THE SUFI MOVEMENT
THE word Sufis an adjective from suf, wool, and its common meaning is derived from the
fact that from the ninth century the practice of wearing a white woollen robe
became normal among Muslim mystics. Both the practice and the word are found in
the eighth century, but they were then exceptional.3 There is an important
sense, of course, in which Islamic mysticism begins with Muhammad himself. It is
difficult to be certain about details, for all we have to go on is what we
deduce from the Quran and from the Traditions-and the Traditions themselves
are often dubious. Yet in general it is clear that Muhammad had profound
mystical experiences, which both stirred him to the depths and were a .source
of spiritual power to him. How his experiences are to be described in terms of
the later systematization of stations and states is a question that may be
neglected here; for one thing he was probably much less conscious of his inner
life than were the later mystics. What is beyond doubt is that his inner
experiences were such that they gave him a firm conviction that God was real.
This conviction supported the basic Islamic conception of the true nature of human
life-activity in accordance with Gods commands, leading to the eternal bliss
of Paradise.
From
the lifetime of Muhammad onwards, there were Muslims to whom the element of
piety or spirituality in the Quran made a strong appeal. In the earliest days
such Muslims were nearly all Arabs. With the conversion of the inhabitants of
Iraq there came into Islam many persons who had been in touch with the
Christian mystical tradition; and it is mainly among non-Arabs that mysticism
in the strict sense develops. The most prominent figure of the seventh and
early eighth century was al-Hasan al-Basri (643-728).5 While most of his thought
and teaching is along the line of asceticism, he occasionally touches on the
conception of love towards God. He had a great influence on his contemporaries
and successors, and the names and sayings have been recorded of many
ascetic-mystics who lived during the eighth and ninth centuries.
Other
important figures are those of al-Junayd (d. 9io) and al-Hallaj (d.922).
Although the latter was executed for heresy, Louis Massignon, who has studied
his life and teaching in great detail, maintains that his essential aim (and
also that of al-Junayd) was to make the spiritual energy generated in the lives
of the ascetics and mystics a fructifying and vitalizing agency in the life of
the whole community as it pursued its essential aim of living according to
Gods commands and thereby attaining Paradise.6 The-position of
these two men is in contrast to various aberrations which Massignon labels
intellectualism, libertarianism, dualism and monism? These faults may occur in
combination. Intellectualism is exaggeration of the importance of the human
intellect or reasoning faculty (at the expense of revelation). Similarly
libertarianism is exaggeration of the importance of the human will and human
effort. It is often associated with monism, that is, exaggeration of Gods
immanence, leading to assertions of the mystics identity with God. A notable
example of this is the celebrated or notorious Abu-Yazid al-Bistami (d. 875},
who gives the impression of aiming at control of the world of inner experience
through his own efforts, employing various ascetical practices and techniques
(some perhaps derived from India).8 The fourth aberration, dualism,
is undue exaggeration of Gods transcendence and is found in circles usually
regarded as theologically conservative.
There
was much mysticism during the tenth and eleventh centuries. Mysticism had
become a part of the general life of the Islamic community. It was not
something separated and isolated, as some Western accounts of the subject
suggest, but belonged to the ordinary life of Muslims. Occasionally little
coteries of sufis might withdraw into seclusion; but at the same time a
surprisingly large number of the scholar-jurists, of whom there are
biographical notices, are said to have been Sufis. In other words, the mystics
were not a sect apart but shared in the disputes of the community about matters
of theology and jurisprudence and included men of the most divergent views in
these respects. Thus the struggle between the various mystical doctrines or
aberrations was not entirely cut off from the other intellectual struggles of
the period. The most outstanding mystic of the century before al-Ghazali is probably
al-Qushayri (d. 1072), who was also a Shaft ite jurist. Like several other men,
he aimed at a synthesis of Asharite dogmatics and certain mystical elements,
but his synthesis is adjudged insufficient by Massignon? The situation
demanded a radical rethinking of the whole of Islamic theology, and the
conservative ethos of Islam made this incredibly difficult. Al-Ghazali later
made a more strenuous effort of the same kind, but whether he was more
successful must remain doubtful.
One of
the aspects of the Sufi movement to which comparatively little attention has
been given is its relation to contemporary history and social conditions. It is
held that the early ascetic trends were a reaction to the wealth and luxury
which came to the leading men of the Islamic empire along with their vast
conquests; 10 and this seems to be true of the earliest period. A little later
there are traces of attacks by the ascetics and mystics on the worldliness and
hypocrisy of the scholar-jurists. In a way the faults of these men were more
serious than those of a ruler, for they were the heart and conscience of
Islamic society. From the first, Islam had been protesting against worldliness
and the materialistic pursuit of wealth (in the case of the rich merchants of
Mecca), and it was thus a disaster for its spiritual leaders to become worldly
and materialistic.
It is
permissible to wonder why, about the year boo, there should have been a
flowering of the higher mysticism in men like al-Junayd and al-Hallaj; but the
most that can be done here is to give some simple suggestions towards a
solution of the problem. It seems most likely that here, as in the general
study of the life of al-Ghazali, fuller understanding is to be gained by
attending closely to the position of the scholar-jurists in the community and
their attitudes to the rulers and the common people. Much had been happening in
the ninth century. At the beginning there had been the work of ash-Shag!
in bringing greater objectivity to the bases of law by insisting on Traditions,
duly transmitted, of the words or acts of Muhammad. This produced later in the
century the standard collections of sound Traditions by al-Bukhari (d. 870)
and Muslim (d. 875). By giving greater intellectual coherence to legal doctrine
these developments must have strengthened the position of the scholar-jurists,
but at the same time must have made them more of a closed corporation. The
latter point has its sinister aspect when it is remembered that the Mihna or
Inquisition of 833-849 had demonstrated the complete domination of
the scholar-jurists as a class and corporation by the rulers. The Inquisition
was eventually given up for reasons of state and not because of the resistance
of Ahmad ibn-Hanbal and one or two others.
From this time on the scholar-jurists,
with hardly any exceptions, are wholly subservient to the government. Men who
have not the courage to stand for Islamic law in its purity soon lose their
zeal for that purity; instead, they become filled with desires for worldly
wealth, position and power.12
The
years from about 900 to 1100 saw fresh vicissitudes. For half a century or more
after 945 Baghdad was under the rule of the Shiite Buwayhid sultans. Though the
Sunnite scholar-jurists continued to have official recognition, their power was
somewhat less, and it was difficult to maintain even this without becoming more
involved in court intrigues. All this would tend to make the scholar-jurists
still more self-seeking. After the unsettled years that followed the decline in
Buwayhid power, the advent of the Seljuqs in 1055 brought a measure of peace.
When a little later the Seljuq government, guided by Nizam-al-Mulk, decided to
support and indeed promote Ash`arism, the dependence of the scholar-jurists on
the rulers was, if anything, increased. The merging of the class of
scholar-jurists with that of secretaries (civil servants), which had been
proceeding for at least two centuries, was almost completed. One of the results
was the succumbing of the scholar-jurists to the politicians disease of
worldliness and materialism -an epidemic to which al-Ghazalis criticismsi3
bear witness.
This
then is the situation in which the suf i movement flourished. The sufis were
those members of the intellectual class who had a genuine spiritual concern
which had not been choked and killed by worldliness. The forces of worldliness
were so strong in political and judicial circles that it was impossible for
such men to express their spiritual aspirations in public activity. Moreover in
many respects a superficial conformity with minimum Islamic standards had been
attained.
In
these circumstances it was natural that the higher spiritual aspirations should
seek to express themselves in the cultivation of the inner life. Here they were
free from the domination of the system-the rigidified body of Islamic legal
thought-with all the worldly and materialistic political attitudes now
associated with it. In certain cases such a turning from public activity to the
inner life would rightly be regarded as escapisma refusal to face up to
difficulties. Here, however, the change seems to be justified. On the one hand,
the worldliness woven into the context of social and political life made it
virtually impossible to realize further spiritual aims in an external way in
this context. On the other hand, the vision of man and his place in the
universe (which was the essence of Islam) had guided and inspired men to a
realization of the vision in the external forms of Islamic society, and this
very success suggested the need for a switch to greater emphasis on the inner
life and the channelling of efforts in this direction. Thus the adoption of the
mystic life is not simply a refusal to face difficulties. The spiritual vision
which had hitherto guided the development of Islamic religion was itself
pointing to greater concentration on the inner life.
2 THE CRISIS OF 1095
In his
autobiography, Deliverance from Error, al-Ghazali
appears to say that he turned to the study of Sufism only after he had found no
satisfaction in his study of theology, philosophy and Batinism. Despite this,
however, he must have had contacts with Sufism at a much earlier period. The
guardian to whom he and his brother were entrusted on his fathers death is
called a Sufi.+ While he was a student at Tus, also, he seems to have bad as a
spiritual director a man called Yusuf an-Nassaj, to whom he related his dreams
and by whom his character was
polished; unfortunately nothing more is known about this man. 5 Al-Juwayni,
under whom al-Ghazali was studying theology at Nishapur from 1077 to 1o85, was
sympathetic to Sufism. Another professor at Nishapur at this period, under whom
al-Ghazali worked, was al-Farmadhi; though some of his lectures may have been
on jurisprudence (which he had studied under the elder al-Ghazali), he was a
pupil of al-Qushayri and had become a recognized leader of the Sufis in Tus and
Nishapur.I6 He had been accepted by Nizamal-Mulk, and indeed his
standing with him was such that he was able to criticize the viziers faults to
his face. 7 Since another of his pupils was the son (al-Hasan)
of al-Ghazalis first teacher of jurisprudence at Tus (Ahmad ar-Radhakani),I8
it is clear that al-Ghazali was moving in circles that were very favourable to
Sufism. It is also clear, however, that after some instruction and a limited
amount of mystical practice al-Ghazali became more interested in theology and
philosophy and neglected mysticism.
According
to Deliverance from Error al-Ghazali
was greatly concerned in his student days and in the immediately following
years with the quest for certainty. His first crisis, when for a time he was a
complete sceptic, arose from the realization that the methods he had been
employing did not give absolute certainty. He had probably begun the study of
philosophy before this crisis, and he may have reached the point of seeing that
in theology and metaphysics the philosophers did not follow a strict logical
method. At the close of the period of scepticism he found himself able to
accept some basic principles because of a light from God; as we might put it,
he saw directly, or had an immediate intuition, that these principles were
true. In 1095 when the second crisis came upon him he already had a
steadfast faith in God, prophethood and the Last Day.20 Despite his way of putting
things in Deliverance from Error, which
makes it appear that he was making a personal search for truth in his study of
Batinism, it seems unlikely that there was much personal engagement; he was
primarily fulfilling a duty imposed on him by the caliph, though in doing so he
may have come to understand more fully the place of Muhammad in the community.
In keeping with all this the crisis of 1095 came upon him at a time when his
dominant aim was not to find intellectual certainty but to achieve a satisfying
life, a life worthy of Paradise. This may be seen from his own description of
the crisis, of which the following is an abbreviated
version.21
Lastly I turned to the way of
the mystics. I knew that in their path there has to be both knowledge and activity,
and that the object of the latter is to purify the self from vices and faults
of character. Knowledge was easier for me than activity. I began by reading
their books ... and obtained a thorough intellectual understanding of their
principles. Then I realized that what is most distinctive of them can be
attained only by personal experience (`taste-dhawq),
ecstasy and a change of character. ... I saw clearly that the mystics were
men of personal experience not of words, and that I had gone as far as possible
by way of study and intellectual application, so that only personal experience
and walking in the mystic way were left.
In my
previous studies and in my practical living I had reached a steadfast faith in
God, prophethood and the Last Day; and these principles had become firmly fixed
in me not through logical proof but by various external and internal causes
which cannot be comprehended in detail. I was convinced that the happiness of
the world to come is to be attained only by a God fearing life and the
discipline of desire, and that the essential thing is to sever the attachment
of the heart to this world by turning from the sphere of deception to that of
eternity, and by earnestly seeking to draw near to God. This could only be
done, too, by rejecting wealth and position and by escaping from entanglements
and commitments.
When I
considered my circumstances, I saw I was deeply involved in affairs, and that
the best of my activities, my teaching, was concerned with branches of
knowledge which were unimportant and worthless. I also examined my motive in
teaching and saw that it was not sincere desire to serve God but that I wanted
an influential position and widespread recognition. I was in no doubt that I
stood on an eroding sandbank, and was in imminent danger of hell-fire if I did
not busy myself with mending my ways.
I kept
thinking about this for a time, as long as it remained a matter of choice. One
day I would decide to leave Baghdad and escape from my involvements; the next
day I would give up the decision. I would put one foot forward, and draw the
other back. Whenever morning found me with a genuine longing to seek the world
to come, evening saw it reduced to nothing by the attack of a host of desires.
Worldly desires were trying to keep me chained where I was, while the herald of
faith was summoning, To the road! To the road! Little of
life is left, and before you is a long journey. Your intellectual and practical
involvements are hypocrisy and delusion. If you do not prepare for the future life
now, when will you prepare; if you do not sever your attachments now, when will
you sever them? At this I would be roused to make a firm decision to run
away and escape. Afterwards Satan would return and say, `This is a passing
mood; do not give in to it, for it will quickly cease. If you yield and leave
this important and influential position, where you are free from petty
annoyances and immune from the attacks of enemies, you may perhaps again
experience its attraction and find difficulty in returning.
For
almost six months beginning with July 1095 I was torn between the attraction of
worldly desires and the summons of the world to come. In that month the matter
ceased to be one of choice and became one of necessity. God parched my tongue
and I was prevented from teaching. I would make an effort to teach one day for
the sake of my audience, but my tongue would not utter a word. This impediment
in speech produced grief in my heart; my digestion was affected, and I could
hardly swallow anything. My general health declined, and the physicians,
realizing that the source of the trouble was in the heart, despaired of
successful treatment, unless the anxiety of the heart could be relieved.
Aware of my impotence and without the power of choice, I took
refuge with God, driven to do so because I had no resource left. He answered
me, he `who answers the one driven to him, when he calls on him (Quran 27.
62/63). He made it easy for my heart to turn from position, wealth, children
and friends. I made public my decision to set out for Mecca, but my private
plan was to travel to Syria, for I did not want the caliph and all my friends
to learn of my decision to spend some time in Syria. This stratagem for leaving
Baghdad I neatly carried out, and was resolved never to return.
Among the religious leaders of Iraq there was much talk about
me, for none thought it possible that my abandonment of everything could have a
religious ground. Knowing no better, they considered that I had attained to the
climax of a religious career. People in general were confused in their
explanations. Those far from Iraq supposed I was apprehensive of ill-treatment
by the rulers. Those close to the rulers, who observed how they sought me out
and how I kept aloof from them, took the view that this was a supernatural
affair, due to some evil influence which had come over the people of Islam and
the circle of the scholars.
One
important point in this account is that al-Ghazali was dissatisfied with the
subjects he was teaching. From his criticisms of the religious sciences in
the first book of The Revival it
would appear that he was thinking of the branches of jurisprudence chiefly
cultivated at this time-and this is a ground for holding that he lectured on
jurisprudence at least as much as on theology. Much attention was given to the
study of the differences between the main legal rites and to the
elaboration of sections of the Sharia or revealed law which were of little
practical application. Such subjects undoubtedly gave men little help in
leading a godly and upright life. In this al-Ghazali was correct. What is
surprising, however, is that he made no attempt to use his position and
influence to have changes made in the curriculum. This at least is the natural
reaction of a modem scholar, even when it is remembered that changes in the
curriculum would be much more difficult in the age of al-Ghazali. Further
reflection, however, suggests other considerations. Perhaps al-Ghazali felt
that the whole system was so permeated by false values that a change in the
curriculum, even if it could be effected, would be of little avail. He would
presumably have liked to include the moral and devotional subjects of
which he writes in The Revival of the
Religious Sciences; but it might have been difficult to find people to
lecture in these, and they would not have been adequate training for young
lawyers.
His
abandonment of any attempt to reform higher education is also connected with
the second important point which appears in his account of the crisis-his
distrust of his own motives. He felt
he was in grave danger of hell, and this chiefly on account of
his worldliness.
He
would seem to have come to the conclusion that he personally, because of his
temperament, was unable to be immersed in the life of the higher circles of
Baghdadian society without becoming contaminated by the prevalent worldliness.
He evidently did not feel that he was able, like his master al-Farmadhi, to
speak to the great ones about their faults. He was, of course, more involved in
the system than al-Farmadhi. He had practically the leading position among the
intellectuals of Baghdad, and presumably maintained a standard of
life in keeping with this position-and that in a world where the outward
signs of status were reckoned important. Had he attempted to take an
independent line in such circumstances, the result would certainly have been
unfortunate. He would be unlikely to accomplish much, and he would gain
ignominy for himself and hardships for his family. Freedom from worldly involvements
seemed to be a necessary condition for any attempt to bring about a reform.
If it is thought that such an
attitude shows undue concern for the welfare of a mans own soul at the expense
of the welfare of society, it should be remembered that this attitude
has deep roots in Islamic history. As early as the first century of Islam men
began to have scruples about receiving payment from the rulers for services in
judicial or legal matters. Originally-that is, in the days when all Muslims
were receiving adequate stipends from the public treasury-such services seem to
have been given without any special payment, and for long this was held up as
an ideal. Some men went so far as to hold that such services should not be
performed even without payment, since this degree of contact with worldly
rulers was corrupting. Long before al-Ghazalis time, however, it had become
the usual practice for judges and similar officials to be paid. Yet the old
ideal was not completely dead. Al-Masudi (d. 956) tells of a man
who, when he first knew him, accepted poverty gladly, but who later became a
judge and completely changed in character for the worse 22
Two
views have been put forward in recent times which give a somewhat different
account from the above of the motives for al-Ghazalis departure from Baghdad.
At the turn of the century Duncan Black Macdonald made the suggestion that the
withdrawal from teaching might have something to do with al-Ghazalis being persona non grata with the sultan
Barkiyaruq.23 More recently Farid Jabre has argued with greater vehemence that
the dominant motive was fear of being assassinated by the Batinites.24
Macdonalds
suggestion about the difficulties with Barkiyaruq was probably not intended to
do more than call attention to a secondary factor, since he accepted
al-Ghazalis conversion to the mystic life as genuine. The chief arguments
were the coincidence of dates and al-Ghazalis implication in the recognition
by the caliph of Barkiyaruqs rival Tutush for a time in 1094. It was in February
1095 that it became clear, with the death of Tutush, that Barkiyaruq
was victor in the struggle with him (which had lasted since the death of
Malikshah in November 1092). Al-Ghazalis illness began in July 1095, and he
left Baghdad in November. Again, Barkiyaruqs death was in late December 1104,
and it was some eighteen months later that al-Ghazali returned to teaching at
Nishapur. Because of this correspondence of dates, some causal connection
cannot be ruled out. On the whole, however, it seems unlikely. In the tangled
politics of the time, men frequently appeared to change sides. Barkiyaruq was
generally on good terms with Fakhr-al-Mulk, a son of Nizam-al-Mulk who had
inherited something of his talents and his policies, and who was later
responsible for al-Ghazalis return to teaching at Nishapur. With this powerful
support it is not credible that al-Ghazalis trifling fault would have
necessitated his departure from his post at Baghdad and he himself asserts that
he was courted by the rulers. There may be a grain of truth in the suggestion,
however, in so far as the vicissitudes of the years after 1092 and the need for
maintaining a delicate balance on the political tight-rope may have helped to
convince al-Ghazali that nothing of what he was interested in could be achieved
through politics and his semi-political position in Baghdad.
Jabres
views, which to begin with appear to be an explanation of al-Ghazalis
departure from Baghdad, develop into an interpretation of his whole career. Of
his dogmatic theology Jabre writes: he thus repeated against the Batinites
what Ash`ari had done two centuries earlier against the Mutazilites: starting
from their own principles he rethought Sunnite dogma for himself and for his
contemporaries. He even goes so far as to say: from 486/1093 this (sc. the work of Ghazali) had a single
aim: to substitute, in the belief of his contemporaries, for the infallibility
of the Batinite imam that of the Prophet, the sole intermediary between God and
man .25 Now these are palpable exaggerations. It is true
that al-Ghazali sometimes speaks (as in Deliverance
from Error) of Muhammad as the infallible imam of the Muslims in general.
But there is not a single section of his chief dogmatic work The Golden Mean in Belief that is seriously
affected by this conception. The same is true of The Revival of the Religious Sciences; everywhere
Muhammad is the great exemplar, according to the usual Sunnite outlook, but
nowhere is there an advance on this and an insistence on his infallibility as a
source of knowledge. While the reaction to Batinism may have contributed
something to these works, it cannot have been more than a minor factor.
Even as
an explanation of al-Ghazalis outward conduct fear of assassination by the
Batinites is not adequate. Jabre argues that, while al-Ghazali may genuinely
have felt that he was too worldly, this fault could have been corrected without
leaving his position in Baghdad, and that therefore something further is
required to explain his departure, and that this must be fear of imminent
danger to his life.25 Yet, even if it is admitted that such a fear
may explain the departure from Baghdad, it does not explain why al-Ghazali
chose the life of a Sufi and cultivated mystical experience so assiduously;
there were other ways open to him of becoming inconspicuous. Indeed, it is
difficult to see how fear of assassination, which involves attaching greater
importance to this world than to the world to come, could lead to al-Ghazalis
intensity in preparing for the world to come. Large tracts of his conduct are
only to be explained by a genuine belief in the Last judgement, and a man with
a firm belief of this kind would not be afraid of death as such but only as
reducing his time for preparing himself to be judged. If there was a real
danger of his being assassinated, this must be how it affected al-Ghazali. This
is in accordance with a passage on which Jabre lays some emphasis, in which
al-Ghazali is reported to have spoken of the opening of a door of fear;27
but he went on to say, not that this caused him to leave Baghdad, but that it
led him to fuller ascetical practices and deeper mystical experiences.
Whether
there was any danger of assassination, such as Jabre supposes, must remain
doubtful. Though Nizam-al-Mulk had been assassinated in 1092, it is not clear
that assassination had been adopted by the Batinites as a regular practice
before 1095; most of the examples come after that. It is also worth noticing
that the danger was greater when al-Ghazali returned to teaching in 1106, and
that his new patron, Fakhr-al-Mulk, was assassinated a month or two after his
return. It is further not clear that al-Ghazali was the kind of person the
Batinites murdered-the caliph, for example, was surely in greater
danger. Ones respect for Jabres arguments is not increased when one finds
him, without any statement of reasons, disregarding accepted conclusions, such
as Goldzihers dating of the Mustazahiri (his
first book in refutation of the Batinites) after The Incoherence of the Philosophers.28 More serious is
his interpretation of some statements that certain philosophical circles were
attracted to Batinism as implying that it was a section of the Batinites who
were attacked in The Incoherence; it
should have been obvious that no philosophically-minded person can at the same
time hold that truth is reached by syllogistic reasoning and by appeal to the
pronouncements of an infallible imam.
It is
important to see this matter in perspective. A perusal of the chronicles of the
period by Ibn-al-Athir makes it clear that there were many dangers threatening
men in political life besides that from the Batinites. There may have been some
personal threat to al-Ghazali from the Batinites of which we know nothing; but
even apart from this there was much to make him aware that life was precarious.
A sense of the precariousness of his life, whatever its source and whatever its
intensity, is not sufficient to account for all his intellectual and spiritual
development, but it would certainly contribute to the growth of his
dissatisfaction with the circumstances in which the intellectual of the time
had to work and with the quality of life that was possible. This
dissatisfaction is the key to al-Ghazalis life; he expressly states it in the
opening book of The Revival; and, as
the present study is trying to show, he had good grounds for being
dissatisfied.
3 LIFE AS A SUFI
Before leaving Baghdad in
November 1095 al-Ghazali had made arrangements for the education of his
children, partly, it would seem, from his own wealth, and partly from
educational trusts which were numerous in Iraq. Doubtless he also made
provision for his wife or wives, in so far as that was not already done in the
marriage contract, but nothing is reported about this since in Islamic society
it was impolite to mention wives. After this he gave away the remainder of his
wealth, and thus committed himself to living the life of a poor Sufi.
In
Damascus, where he first went, he says he spent nearly two years, passing
most of his time in solitude or retirement and engaging in devotional
exercises. It was presumably a life similar to that which he describes in The Beginning of Guidance,29 and
which is based on a rule similar to that of Christian monastic communities.
Many stories most of them perhaps apocryphal are told of his residence in
Damascus. It seems likely, however, that he was unable to conceal his identity
altogether, and that many serious-minded persons in Damascus took advantage of
the presence of this great scholar among them. This may be why, in order to be
alone, he would go up the minaret of the mosque at Damascus and shut himself in
for the whole day.
In his
own later account of this time30 he says he went on to Jerusalem,
and he must have spent some days or weeks there, engaged in solitary prayer and
meditation in the Dome of the Rock, the site of Solomons temple and the
alleged site of Abrahams sacrifice of his son and of Muhammads miraculous
night-journey to heaven. From Jerusalem he decided to make the pilgrimage to
Mecca. On the way he prayed at the tomb of Abraham at Hebron and that of
Muhammad at Medina. Then, his account continues, my concerns and the appeals
of my children drew me to my homeland, and I went back, after I had been the
furthest of mortals from returning. He still cultivated solitude, but found it
difficult to secure the peace he desired, for distractions were many.
Nevertheless,
he persevered in his religious exercises, and always returned from his
distractions to his quest for inner peace and illumination. At this stage he
continued, he says, for ten years. A deeper understanding came to him of the
principles of religion, and he was convinced that the way of life he was
following was the truest and highest.
In this
later autobiographical account there are many difficulties. From soon after his
death there have been widely divergent views about the details of his
movements. Some of the early biographical notices say that he spent ten years
in Syria, having returned there after his pilgrimage to Mecca. Now it seems
probable that he returned to Damascus, and that he regards his pilgrimage and
his visit to Jerusalem as belonging to his Damascus period. This is in
accordance with his account, provided that we take his phrase about the
journey to the Hijaz to mean a journey to Mecca and back to Damascus; this
seems to be a reasonable interpretation. It is practically certain, however,
that he did not spend ten years at Damascus. His own words do not necessitate
it; indeed, they suggest that he returned to his homeland not long after his
pilgrimage; the word thumma, then,
seems to indicate an interval but not an unduly long one. He is reported to
have made the pilgrimage in 489 (November-December 1096),31 and also
to have been encountered in Baghdad about June I097.32 There seems
to be no ground for rejecting the first of these dates, and the second fits in
well with most of the relevant facts. The chief remaining difficulty is that
al-Ghazali himself speaks of being nearly two years at Damascus, while, if we
accept this second date, he cannot have been there more than eighteen
months-from November To95 to June 1097-even if the time spent on the pilgrimage
is counted in; it seems best, however, to accept the date and to assume that
al-Ghazali used the phrase nearly two years somewhat loosely. His reference
to ten years will then be to the whole time from his departure from Baghdad
to his making arrangements for a return to teaching at Nishapur (which actually
took place in July 1106). A subordinate reason for thinking he did not spend
ten years in Damascus is that the activity of the Crusaders was beginning,
Jerusalem falling to them in July 1099, and there are no signs of al-Ghazali
being affected by the Crusades.
It has
often been asserted that he paid a visit to Egypt from Damascus. The dating
which has just been argued for leaves time for only the briefest of visits. It
is certainly possible that there was such a visit on the way to or from Mecca.
If it took place, however, it can have been little more than an incident of the
journey, and the absence of any mention of it in Deliverance from Error indicates that it had no spiritual
significance for al-Ghazali.
Another question which might be raised is what al-Ghazali meant by
homeland (watan). Was it Iraq or
Khurasan? He spoke of the excellence of the educational trusts in Iraq in
connection with his arrangements for his children. It is a generally accepted
fact, however, that he spent some time in his native town of Tus before
returning to teaching at the not very distant Nishapur. Since he is not
mentioned in the report of reactions in Baghdad to the fall of Jerusalem in
1099, it has been argued that he had already left.33 Though this
argument is not conclusive, it is likely that he went to Tus about this time
(passing through Hamadhan on the way),34 for some of the biographers place a
stay of several years in Tus before his return to teaching in 1106. Here he
lived a somewhat monastic life, but he also established a hostel or convent (khangdh) and permitted disciples to
share his life; he also discoursed to them on the subjects treated in The Revival of the Religious Sciences. The
names are known of several men who became his disciples at Tus.35
By way
of summarizing the above discussions the following brief account of his
movements from 1095 to 1106 might be given. On leaving Baghdad in November 1095
al-Ghazali proceeded to Damascus and lived quietly there. Towards the end of
1096 he went to Jerusalem. During the months of November and December 1096 be
was engaged in the pilgrimage, perhaps visiting Alexandria on the way. He went
back to Damascus, but not later than June 1097 returned to Baghdad. He spent
some time there, but possibly about 1099 returned to his native town of Tus,
and founded a small institution for the cultivation of the religious life. In
1105 or early in 1106 Fakhr-al-Mulk, the son of Nizam-al-Mulk, who had now
become vizier of the Seljuq prince Sanjar, governor of Khurasan, prevailed upon
al-Ghazali to accept a post-presumably the chief professorship at the Nizamiyya
college at Nishapur. There he took up his duties in July or August 1106. This was the eleventh month of the
Islamic year 499; and al-Ghazali was influenced by a Tradition to
the effect that at the beginning of each century the Islamic community would
have a renewer of religion, since his friends insisted that he was to be the
renewer for the new century.36
There
is not much more of the story to tell. Al-Ghazali continued teaching at
Nishapur for at least three years. A book on legal theory, commonly known as
the Mustasfa and apparently
containing his lectures at Nishapur, was completed in August 1109.37 It
was perhaps a little earlier that he wrote his autobiographical work, Deliverance from Error, since he was still
teaching at Nishapur when he wrote it. At some date after August 1109 he once more gave up teaching and retired to his native town of
Tus. The reason for this retirement we can only conjecture. While personal
difficulties of the kind which led to his withdrawal from Baghdad cannot be
excluded, it is possible that he retired because of failing health and the
beginning of the illness which led to his death on December 18th, 1111. It may well be that he did not return to Tus until 1110 or early 1111; a reference to a
man who studied law with him at Tus seems
to refer to this period, if the source has not confused Nishapur and Tus.
38 Even if his retirement was due to ill-health he must still have been
able to write, since he appears to have completed a small book less than a
fortnight before he died 39 On the day of his death, his brother
Ahmad related, he made his ablutions and performed the dawn worship; he then
asked for his shroud, took it, kissed it and laid it on his eyes with the
words, Obediently I enter into the presence of the King; then he stretched
out his feet, faced the qibla (the
direction of Mecca), and before daybreak was dead.40
The
book he completed just before his death has the title, The Restraining of the Commonalty from the Science of Theology, and
it is worth looking for a moment at its contents. It purports to be a reply to
a questioner. You have asked me about the Traditions which the ignorant and
erring Hashwiyya (a sect or tendency) imagine to necessitate anthropomorphism;
for they believe that God has a form, a hand, a mouth, a foot, that he comes
down, moves his position, sits on the throne, and so on, in accordance with the
literal meaning of the Traditions; they also claim that their belief is that of
the fathers (salaf); so you want me
to explain what is the belief of the fathers and to show what the ordinary man
must believe about these Traditions.4i The first chapter deals with
the true position of the fathers concerning the Traditions in question, and
maintains that according to the fathers the ordinary man has seven duties with
regard to these anthropomorphic conceptions: he must realize that they do not
imply that God is corporeal; he must believe them since they come from God (in
the case of Quranic conceptions) or from Muhammad; he must realize his own
inability to understand them positively; he must not ask about them, or try to
explain them by using other words, or even puzzle over them in his own mind,
but must accept the views of those who have knowledge of such matters. The
second chapter deals with the truth of the doctrine of the fathers, and proves
it both by reason and from Tradition; the general rational proof makes the
following points: the Prophet was best informed about the position of man with
regard to the future life; he passed on to mankind all that was revealed to
him; the closest Companions were best informed about the meaning of his words;
these discouraged men from investigating the conceptions further. The third
chapter deals with miscellaneous questions, ending up with a statement of the
six grades of belief: belief after strict proof, complete at every step; belief
after proof based on premisses not strictly proved but generally accepted by
scholars; belief based on rhetorical proofs; belief in the statement of a
trustworthy person; belief in a statement made in circumstances generally
accepted as satisfactory; belief in a statement because one wants to believe it
without considering if the informant is trustworthy.
There
is much in this little book which is worthy of careful study, and all that can
be done here is to notice some points relevant to present concerns. Firstly, it
is directed against people whom al-Ghazali calls Hashwiyya, and these are
presumably Hanbalites and TraditioniSts,42 and perhaps also the
Karramites. Secondly, one of the main concerns of the book is to avoid
anthropomorphism (tashbih) or the
literal interpretation of such expressions as the hand of God; yet at the
same time al-Ghazali wants ordinary men to accept these expressions with simple
faith without engaging in rational discussion of them. This is his programme of
a via media which he sketches briefly
in The Niche for Lights; 43 he seeks to avoid a literal interpretation which implies
corporeality in God and an allegorical interpretation which abandons the
scriptural conception. Thirdly, the book is presumably directed to scholars and
theologians, and there is no
suggestion of a degree of understanding beyond theirs, though nothing to
exclude various levels of understanding among them.
It is important to notice these points. It is still often stated or
assumed that there was a closing phase in al-Ghazalis life when he abandoned
Asharism and became a Neoplatonist. This book, completed a few days before his
death, shows him thinking and arguing essentially as an Asharite; even if he
had earlier gone beyond Asharism in some of his speculations (such as those
about the nature of prophethood and the immediate experience of the mystics),
he has not abandoned any Islamic dogma or any of the central positions of
Asharism. From this it follows that works of a Neoplatonic character ascribed
to al-Ghazali must be regarded as spurious. The only possible exception to this
is, if it can be shown that a specific work was written between about 1091 and
1096, which is the time when his enthusiasm for philosophy was greatest. To
this period belongs a work on ethics mainly from the standpoint of Greek
philosophy which is genuine at least in part, but to which he never refers in
his later books44-presumably
because he came to think about ethical questions more in traditional Islamic
terms. That any other of the works of doubtful authenticity can be ascribed to
him at this period has not yet been shown. The careful study of dates by Maurice
Bouyges, however, seems to have cut the ground from the idea that he turned to
Neoplatonism in his closing years. Even the tendency to treat ordinary men
differently from scholars--which might suggest that he was concealing esoteric
views-is to be found in his thoroughly Asharite work on dogmatics, The Golden Mean in Belief 45
4 THE REVIVAL OF
THE RELIGIOUS SCIENCES
It is
universally acknowledged that al-Ghazalis greatest work is The Revival of the Religious Sciences. It is
by far the lengthiest, usually occupying four volumes of some fifteen
hundred large pages. A complete English translation would probably have at
least two million words. This great work belongs to his period as a Sufi. A
small part of it, known as The Epistle
from Jerusalem, was probably composed separately during his visit to
Jerusalem in 1096, and it may be that the work as a whole was not conceived
till later. He would require time to settle down after the crisis of 1095
before he could contemplate such a work. It doubtless took several years to
compose, though it has to be remembered that Arabic can be written almost as
fast as shorthand and that al-Ghazali appears to have been a fast worker.
Various literary problems connected .with it have not yet been adequately
studied-whether it was written in order as it stands, or whether some portions
(such as the beginning of the third quarter) are later additions; how it is
related to the shorter abbreviation known as The Book of the Forty and to the longer Persian abridgement, The Alchemy o f Happiness. Clearly any
attempt to assess al-Ghazalis achievement must pay considerable attention to
this work.
The Revival is divided into four
quarters, and each of these into ten books.46 The first quarter is
entitled matters of service (sc. of God) or, as we might say, cult
practices. The first book, as has been mentioned earlier, deals with knowledge
or science, and is doubtless intended as an introduction to the whole. The
seven chapters into which it is divided deal with a number of different topics,
but the main concern is to indicate which subjects of study or sciences are
of importance for a devout Muslim, and in what measure. In various places there
occur the criticisms of the scholar-jurists of the day, which have already been
noted. The second book is about the basic principles of the creed, and
contains: (a) an elaboration of the Confession of Faith I bear witness that
there is no god but God, Muhammad is the Messenger of God; (b) a discussion of
education in matters of doctrine; (c) a statement of Islamic doctrine in four
sections, each with ten points; (d) a discussion of the relation between faith
and Islam, that is, between being a believer and being a Muslim. In one sense
this is still introductory material, but in another sense the Confession of
Faith might be regarded as a cult practice.
The
remaining eight books of the first quarter deal with: ritual purity (ablutions
before worship, etc.), formal prayers or worship, tithing, fasting, the
pilgrimage to Mecca, the recitation of the Quran, private prayer, and
supererogatory and extracanonical devotions. Each practice is usually
introduced by Quranic verses and Traditions justifying it, and by sayings of
Muhammad and devout Muslims advocating and praising it. How to carry it out is
explained in very great detail-some of this can be very surprising to Western
students not accustomed to a legalistic outlook in matters of religious
practice. Al-Ghazali, however, is always concerned not merely that a mans
external practice should be flawless, but that he should also have the
appropriate inner attitudes and understand something of the deeper reasons for
what he does. In short, al-Ghazali looks upon the external practices as means
by which a man becomes near to God and prepares himself for the life of the
world to come.
The
second quarter is entitled customs and deals with the external aspects of
ordinary life outside the practice of the cult. For the Muslim practically all
the matters dealt with come within the sphere of the revealed law or Shania,
though we should classify some as ethical, some as legal and some as questions
of etiquette. There are books about eating and drinking, marriage, earning one
living and engaging in business, relations with friends and relatives, the
life of retirement, travelling, and the use of music. One book entitled Of the
lawful and unlawful is really about questions of conscience. Another might be
said to be about reforming society and improving its tone. The last book is a
word-picture of Muhammad as the exemplar of all the qualities extolled in the
earlier books. Though there is much secular detail in this quarter,
al-Ghazali never loses sight of the contribution of the things he discusses to
mans spiritual growth.
The
last two quarters deal explicitly with mans inner life, and are entitled
respectively things leading to destruction and things leading to salvation
or, as we might say vices and virtues. The first book of the third quarter
is an introductory account of the mysteries of the heart, and is followed by
a book dealing with the improvement of the character in a general way. Then
come books on the control of the appetites for food and sexual intercourse, on
the weaknesses of the tongue, on anger, on worldliness, on avarice, on
hypocrisy and love of fame, on pride and vanity, and on self-deception. The
books of the fourth quarter are respectively on repentance, on patience and
gratitude (to God), on fear and hope, on poverty and self-discipline, on
asserting Gods unity and trusting in him, on love (for God) and approval (of
his decrees), on sincerity and purity of intention, on self-examination, on
meditation, and on death and the life to come. Thus the second
---End of Part one--
Coming Soon Part two.
E-mail: webmaster
- Sign the Guest
Book - Imam Ghazali Home
Page Information:
This Page was last updated on: 06 Jun 2007 09:44:17 -0400
This page was created April 15, 2003.
© Copyright 2003 by Islamic Philosophy Online, Inc. All rights reserved. A not-for-profit organization dedicated to academic study of Islamic philosophy. Individual content may have its own individual copyrights. See copyright information.