Ghaz?l? and the Perils of Interpretation*
By
Ahmad Dallal
Ab?
??mid al-Ghaz?l? (d. 505/1111) is one of the most celebrated thinkers of
Arabo-Islamic culture. The scope and high quality of al-Ghaz?l?’s prolific
intellectual career reflect not just his genius and ambition, but, in many
ways, mark the culmination of one cultural epoch and the beginning of another.
The continuing interest in and discussion of al-Ghaz?l?, which began in his
life time, assured him a central position in Islamic culture as one of its
constitutive elements and authoritative voices. Reflecting a highly developed
stage in medieval Islamic thought, his works abound in confrontations between
the manifold epistemologies and systems of thought that were adopted and
employed by the various political, sectarian, and ideological groups populating
the Islamic cultural landscape. Richard Frank’s Al-Ghaz?l? and the Ash‘arite School provides perhaps the most
authoritative study to date of the place of Ghaz?l?’s thought in Islamic
theology, and thus merits a full examination on account of the centrality of
the study and its subject matter.
Given the range of his ideas, al-Ghaz?l?
has both inspired and puzzled many of his readers, past and present: some have
seen him as a champion of Islam, while others have vilified him as its enemy.
Others still, like Mu?ammad ibn al-Murta?? (d. 1680) in his famous al-Ma?ajja al-Bay??’,[1] chose to mute their partial criticisms
of al-Ghaz?l?, and to appropriate him by arguing that, at some point toward the
end of his life, he repudiated the objectionable aspects of his thought. Muslim
philosophers are equally represented among al-Ghaz?l?’s numerous critics; they
grudgingly attempted (and perhaps eventually failed) to contain the damage
caused by his attacks, not just from without but also from within their system
of thought. On a more traditional level, some argued that, despite his critique
of philosophy, al-Ghaz?l? was never able to rid himself of residues of this
same philosophy which were ingrained in his thought.[2] In fact, the ambiguity in al-Ghaz?l?’s
position towards philosophy is itself a symptom of the difficult relationship
between the so called ‘Islamic’ and ‘foreign’ sciences in medieval Islamic
cultures, one marked at once by ideological rejection as well as
epistemological attraction.
Modern
scholars have also tried to explain the apparent inconsistencies in the thought
of al-Ghaz?l?, often by positing a chronology behind his psychological and
intellectual profile. According to this approach, al-Ghaz?l? underwent an
existential crisis that led to a transformation in his views. While before this
crisis al-Ghaz?l? was greatly influenced by philosophy, following it he fell
under the spell of gnostic anti-philosophical thought. Perhaps the main
limitation in this view is that philosophical influences can still be traced in
the gnostic and post-crisis works of al-Ghaz?l?. Yet another standard method
for resolving inconsistencies in al-Ghaz?l?’s thought has been to question the
attribution of some of the problematic works to him.[3]
Understandably,
therefore, the various readings of the thought of al-Ghaz?l?, whether direct
and expository or interpretative and reconstructive, have been able to cite
evidence in their support. Reading al-Ghaz?l? is further complicated because it
involves dealing with a whole cultural legacy with its numerous trends and
schools. In a famous reference reflecting past and present difficulties in
assessing the works of al-Ghaz?l?, Ibn Taymiyya says:[4]
... due to his intelligence and sincere
quest, he [al-Ghaz?l?] became aware of the confusion in the method of the
theologians and philosophers. God granted him comprehensive belief--as he says
about himself--and he then hoped to explicate the totality [of his belief]. He
found the views of the masters and the Sufis closer to the truth, and more
worthy of confirmation than the views of the philosophers and the theologians....
Thus he believed that the explication of the totality [of belief] can be
attained solely through this method [of the Sufis]. He had no other method
available to him: the special, exalted prophetic path was blocked before him
due to the little knowledge he had of it, and due to the obscurities he
inherited from the philosophers and the theologians.... Because of this, he was
often critical of these obstacles and the [related] method of knowledge. This,
however, was only due to the [particular kind of] knowledge he adopted, which
shielded him from the truth of the pursuit of the [prophetic] message. For
this, in fact, is not knowledge; it is only philosophical and theological
dogma....
A
group of people that recognized [al-Ghaz?l?’s] virtues and religiosity denied
the attribution of these books [ex. Bid?yat al-Hid?ya and Al-Ma?n?n bihi ‘al?
Ghayri Ahlihi] to him.... Those, however, who are familiar with him and his
circumstances know that these are all his own words because they are aware of
the similarities between the various elements of his discourse. Moreover, he
and people like him, as I said earlier, are restless and they do not adhere to
one firm view, because they have such intelligence and craving [for knowledge]
that they hope to discover the method of the elect....
He
was inclined to philosophy, but he presented it in the guise of Sufism and
Islamic terminology. Because of this, Muslim scholars have responded to him,
including the closest of his companions, Ab? Bakr ibn al-‘Arab?, who said: “our
master Ab? ??mid entered the stomach of the philosophers, then when he wanted
to come out he could not do so.”
Despite differences in style and
judgment, the main points of the argument above bear a striking resemblance to
the central thesis of Richard Frank’s Al-Ghaz?l? and
the Ash‘arite School. Both agree that 1) despite his attacks on
philosophers, al-Ghaz?l? was greatly influenced by philosophy; 2) that he was
critical of traditional methods of acquiring knowledge, including those of the
various religious sciences and theological schools; 3) that students of
al-Ghaz?l?’s works are often confused, and either deny the attribution of
certain works to him, or else argue that there are inconsistencies in his
writings; 4) that despite these ostensible inconsistencies, and although
al-Ghaz?l? did not write a single coherent exposition of his own theological
views, elements of his theology can be traced in his various works; and 5) that
al-Ghaz?l? chose to conceal his real theological views by manipulating
language, and by deliberately using traditional religious idiom to introduce
his own unconventional ideas.
To
be sure, there are also differences between Ibn Taymiyya’s assertions and
Frank’s analysis of the works of al-Ghaz?l?. Ibn Taymiyya, does not illustrate
any of his allegations, and simply refers his reader to several books and
authors who have written responses to al-Ghaz?l?. In contrast, Frank provides a
readable, thorough, and systematic interpretation of al-Ghaz?l?’s thought. The
main difficulty in Frank’s close readings is that his representations of
al-Ghaz?l?’s thought are often open to alternative interpretations. I will
devote the remainder of this review to demonstrate this point, but before I
continue it would be useful to outline Frank’s methodology.
Frank
plows through the Ghaz?lian corpus, explores its various layers, and tries to
establish the nature of the relationship between these layers. The result
provides a detailed analysis of the thought of al-Ghaz?l? and its relation to
the traditional teachings of the Ash‘arite school. Although many of Frank’s
final conclusions are not new, what makes this book unique is the way in which
he painstakingly reconstructed the thought of al-Ghaz?l?.
Owing
to the abstract nature of the subject, studies of theological and philosophical
topics tend to be dry and difficult to follow. Yet in this book, Frank presents
the material in a lucid and systematic manner, while managing to convey the
complexity of the original debates and systems of thought, all fully informed
by his intimate knowledge of the Islamic theological tradition in general and
the Ash‘arite tradition in particular.
By
working back and forth through them, rather than taking a strictly
chronological approach in his analysis, Frank tries to discern a consistent
system of thought underlying al-Ghaz?l?’s texts. Grounding his interpretations
in close textual readings, he examines and reinterprets many texts by
al-Ghaz?l?. He then uses his renditions of these texts to reconstruct
al-Ghaz?l?’s whole system of thought. His focus, therefore, is on al-Ghaz?l?’s
intentions as revealed in reconstituted texts, and not on any preconceived
notions of what these intentions may be. Moreover, Frank (87) argues that
“...one should not try to separate his [al-Ghaz?l?’s] work (or parts of his
works) into esoteric and exoteric, as if some were addressed to the religious
scholars at large and others, containing his “real position” to some elite
fraternity. His works are, rather, to be viewed together as the essentially
consistent, albeit rhetorically modulated, address to his fellow Sh?fi‘is and
to the ‘ulama at large.”[5] In only one instance, Frank (91)
maintains that “al-Ghaz?l? seems manifestly to deny what he in fact believes.” He
adds, however, that this is an exception, the rule being that al-Ghaz?l?
generally tends not to say things he does not believe in. According to Frank,
therefore, al-Ghaz?l?’s texts may not be interpreted under the assumption that
they mean the opposite of what they say. However, al-Ghaz?l?’s work may be
“rhetorically modulated,” and the meanings Frank assigns to the texts, or what
he considers to be intentional ambivalence on the part of al-Ghaz?l?, are often
based on his estimation of the intended audience of the particular work under
examination.
Al-Ghaz?l?’s
“higher theology” vs. traditional Ash‘arite theology:
Frank
(100-101) attributes the impression that some have of “gross inconsistency” in
al-Ghaz?l?’s works to the interplay of several factors including: 1) the fact
that “al-Ghaz?l? never composed a complete systematic summary of his theology
in formally conceptual terms”; 2) that his theology is “rather superficial; the
general structure is there, but in a number of places seems incomplete”; and 3)
that al-Ghaz?l? associated himself with the Ash‘arite school “with regards to
teaching and instruction of religious doctrine on a general or elementary
level.” Elsewhere (99) Frank attributes this association to al-Ghaz?l?’s
professional interests and “training under Juwayn? and... his position in the
Ni??miyya....” 4) Finally, according to Frank, the impression of inconsistency
is due to the fact that, despite his formal association with the Ash‘arite
school, al-Ghaz?l? did not hold the “traditional doctrine of the school as his
own, personal madhhab....”
According
to Frank, al-Ghaz?l? was consistent in his reserved attitude towards, and
eventually outright alienation from the Ash‘arite school, and in “deplor[ing]
the theoretical worthlessness of
ordinary kal?m” (98). Al-Ghaz?l?’s
alienation, according to Frank, finds its clearest expression in his later
works, such as the Fay?al[6] and the Ilj?m.[7] Frank also argues (87) that “Where he
[al-Ghaz?l?] presents his thought in unambiguous conceptual terms, the basic
character and structure of the system is clear to see...,” although (Frank, 92)
al-Ghaz?l?’s language “lacks precision,” and after piecing together different
elements from his various texts “the view often remains only that of the
general sense of what he thinks, while important aspects of the matter remain
unexplained.”
In
fact, al-Ghaz?l? proves to be consistent in a number of ways which are,
perhaps, more significant than those emphasized by Frank. Before taking up the
issue of al-Ghaz?l?’s attitude towards traditional Ash‘arism, however, it may
be useful to mention one particular instance of such consistency: al-Ghaz?l?’s
charge that the philosophers are guilty of unbelief on account of their
doctrine of the eternity of the world, their denial of bodily resurrection, and
their assertion that God’s knowledge does not encompass particulars. In most of
his works, including those which, according to Frank, mark al-Ghaz?l?’s
alienation from traditional Ash‘arism, as well as a high level of borrowing
from philosophical doctrine, al-Ghaz?l? either reiterates his main criticisms
of philosophy listed above (Fay?al,
191-2), or explicitly refers his reader to his standard attack on philosophy in
the Tah?fut al-Fal?sifa[8] (for example Mi‘y?r,[9] 191; Mi?akk,[10] 61; Musta?f?,[11] 45-6).
Frank
argues that the traditional Ash‘arite view of kal?m is that it is a “rational metaphysics” (5), “the universal
religious science” (9) that “proves the basic articles of Muslim religious
belief without formal appeal to... religious belief as such” (5). Al-Ghaz?l?’s
view of kal?m, on the other hand, is
ambivalent; not only do the school theologians focus almost exclusively on
disputation, but also the reasoning of kal?m
itself is “merely dialectical” (Frank, 16), and it “cannot yield true
intellectual insight or knowledge of the essential natures of things as they
really are in themselves” (Frank, 17). Later, Frank’s initial references to ambivalence become more conclusive, as
he asserts that “al-Ghaz?l?’s basic theological system is fundamentally
incompatible with the traditional teaching of the Ash‘arite school” (87), and
that al-Ghaz?l? “deplores the theoretical worthlessness of ordinary kal?m--its inherent failure to grasp the
‘true natures of things’” (98). This is not to say that al-Ghaz?l?, according
to Frank, did not associate with traditional Ash‘arism, but his association was
purely formal. Al-Ghaz?l? thus “needed to demonstrate his formal bond to the
Ash‘arite school in terms that would not conflict with his private or interior madhhab” (99). To do this, Frank argues,
al-Ghaz?l? resorted to “rhetorical maneuvers” (18) and linguistic acrobatics as
he sought to “mute, reconcile, rationalize, or override” his conflict with
fellow Ash‘arites (xi). He tried to “bring his own metaphysics... into some
kind of positive relationship with the traditional teaching of the Ash‘arite
school. Since the two are fundamentally incompatible, one of the things he did
was to attempt a kind of harmonization at the level of language” (88). In other
words, according to Frank, al-Ghaz?l? used traditional Ash‘arite language to
express ideas that are incompatible with traditional Ash‘arite doctrine.
Frank
maintains that the level of ambivalence in the works of al-Ghaz?l? differs
according to the purpose of the book and the specific context of its writing.
As a general rule, al-Ghaz?l? tends to be more explicit in expressing his own
metaphysical views, and in using a language that does not conform with the
traditional Ash‘arite idiom, in works written towards the end of his career.
The Mi‘y?r, Mi?akk, Maq?ad,[12] I?ya’,[13] Jaw?hir,[14] Mishk?t,
Arba‘?n,[15] Qis??s,[16] Musta?f?,
and Ilj?m are all works that are not
“consistent with traditional Ash‘arite kal?m
either in language and conception or in theoretical assumptions and
constructs....” (29, also 100).
The
Iqti??d[17] (and, to a lesser extent the Qudsiyya,[18] Frank, chapter 3) is ‘formally’ an Ash‘arite work where,
according to Frank, al-Ghaz?l?’s ambivalence is illustrated. This book is meant
to be a traditional summary manual and, because of that, it uses traditional
Ash‘arite language. It is directed to the simple minds of “average religious
scholars,” and is not a work of “higher speculative theology” (30-31). The book
does not consider the world as a system, but “only as it is God’s making” (36).
For this reason, al-Ghaz?l? does not elaborate his cosmology or his full
theological doctrine in the Iqti??d,
although he makes subtle references to both. Frank adds, however, that in this
book al-Ghaz?l? intentionally avoids saying anything that would contradict his
“higher theology” (which is never stated but only hinted at by al-Ghaz?l? and
reconstructed by Frank). Moreover, Frank maintains (29-30), the arguments and
explanations of the Iqti??d are
significantly different from those of traditional Ash‘arism; in a few cases
al-Ghaz?l? explicitly rejects Ash‘arite doctrine, while in other cases he
deliberately uses vague language in order to give the impression that he is in
conformity with the Ash‘arites (18). In contrast to this attitude toward
traditional Ash‘arism, Frank adds, al-Ghaz?l? makes “frequent, though
irregular, use of Avicenna’s vocabulary.” Frank thus concludes that the Iqti??d can be properly understood only
in light of other clearer works by al-Ghaz?l?.
Frank
typically engages in intricate analysis of words and sentences to demonstrate
al-Ghaz?l?’s ambivalence and close affinity to the Mu‘tazila on a number of
theological points. For example, Frank maintains (36) that al-Ghaz?l? ends up
being “much closer” to the Mu‘tazila than the Ash‘arites when he holds that (a)
“ethical imperatives can be fully rationalized, and (b) ethical necessity... is
a kind of natural necessity, being founded on the obligation to avoid harm to
one’s self.” To illustrate this point of “natural necessity,” Frank goes on to
say that al-Ghaz?l? “in fact holds that God necessarily creates what he creates
and can have created no other universe. This is indicated in the statement (Iqti??d, 43,3), “‘al-qad?m’ [the eternal, a description unique to God] is an
expression for that which exists necessarily in all its aspects” (m? huwa w?jibu l-wuj?di f? jam?‘i jih?tih?).”
The
above quote from al-Ghaz?l? is a stark example of the central problematic in
Frank’s book. His interpretations of various texts by al-Ghaz?l? are not
conclusive. In fact, when read in their immediate textual context, most of
Frank’s interpretations seem improbable. For example, the last quote is taken
from a section in the Iqti??d in
which al-Ghaz?l? denies that God is “spatially located,” and asserts that “God
is not in any one of the six directions,” (39). So al-Ghaz?l? in the above
quotation discusses “directions” and “spatial locations” not “aspects.” In
fact, the Arabic translated by Frank is slightly misquoted, for the original
reads “that which exists necessarily in all directions” (m? huwa w?jibu l-wuj?di min [not f?] jam?‘i al-jih?t [not jih?tih?]) (Iqti??d, 43,3). If there is any doubt as to what al-Ghaz?l? means
by jih?t, it is immediately clarified
as he moves on to say (Iqti??d,
43,4): “If someone says that only God is characterized by the direction of
above, we say....”
The
above problem of interpretation is recurrent throughout Frank’s analysis not
just of the Iqti??d, but other works
by al-Ghaz?l? as well. Other examples dealing with al-Ghaz?l?’s discussion of
causality in the Iqti??d are quoted
by Frank, and these and others will be discussed in the following sections. In
concluding this section, however, two points need to be made: First, that
although al-Ghaz?l? shapes the arguments in his various books with particular
audiences in mind, this does not necessarily mean that he devises deliberate
stratagems to elude traditional theologians or to cover up his “real”
philosophical inclinations. Second, the priorities of the Ash‘arite ideological
program had undergone significant changes between the time of the founder of
the school and al-Ghaz?l?’s time. It is quite possible that al-Ghaz?l? adhered
faithfully to the general outlines of this program, namely to provide
theoretical ammunition for battling the Ism?‘?li B??iniyya and, to a lesser
extent, the philosophers, even if he uses some of the tools of the
philosophers, or even, as some would argue, the Ism?‘?lis. At any rate, there
may still be great value in the now old and frequently made argument that
al-Ghaz?l? agreed with the conclusions of the theologians but did not approve
of their methods, and opposed the conclusions of the philosophers while
subscribing to their methods of demonstration.
Frank
argues that al-Ghaz?l? has his own notion of kal?m as “extended metaphysics” that is quite different from
traditional Ash‘arite kal?m. Like the
earlier kal?m of the Mu‘tazila,
al-Ghaz?l?’s metaphysics constitutes a universal, higher religious science that
is the basis of all other particular sciences. This science is the “measure of
the truth of any and all theological propositions” (11). Furthermore,
al-Ghaz?l? maintains that “knowledge of the essential natures of things as they
really are in themselves” is achievable through demonstrative proof (burh?n), “carried out on premises which
are founded in one of five sources,” all of which are taken from Ibn S?n?
(Frank, 17). Thus while al-Ghaz?l? opposes the conceptual and analytical
tradition of kal?m, he is in favor of
a metaphysics based on philosophy.
As
he does throughout this book, Frank goes through a meticulous analysis of
various quotes in order to reconstruct al-Ghaz?l?’s higher theology and his
real views on philosophy. Here too, however, Frank’s interpretations are
problematic and inconclusive. For example, on the notion that al-Ghaz?l?
believes in a higher theology, Frank maintains (8) that “al-Ghaz?l? speaks of
having insight into the truth ‘by means of speculative reasoning, rational
inquiry and the correct elaboration of logical demonstration’” (kashfu dh?lika... bi l-na?ari wa l-ba?thi
wa-ta?r?ri l-’adillah) (I?y?’, I,
15, 12f.). Now, although al-Ghaz?l? speaks elsewhere of speculative reasoning
and demonstration as the highest form of several ways of achieving certain
knowledge (for example, Ilj?m,
111-2), the immediate textual context of the above I?y?’ statement by al-Ghaz?l? precludes Frank’s interpretation. The
full quotation of al-Ghaz?l? reads: “the first thing that is obligatory on a
legal major (b?ligh) is to learn the
two professions of faith and to understand their meaning... and it is not
obligatory on him to achieve the exposition of this [knowledge] to himself by
means of speculative reasoning, investigation, or the exact formulation of demonstrative
proofs.” (wa laysa yajibu ‘alayhi an
yu?a??ila kashfa dh?lika li nafsihi bil-na?ari wal-ba?thi wa ta?r?ri l-adilla).”
In
a more pertinent example used to illustrate al-Ghaz?l?’s belief in the ultimate
authority of his kind of kal?m, Frank
(8) says: “Classifying religious sciences in Musta?f?, al-Ghaz?l? says that kal?m
is the one that is universal (al-‘ilmu
l-kulliyyu mina l-‘ul?mi l-d?niyyah) (5, 9)... and [it] ultimately
demonstrates the basic truths of the revelation and establishes the principles
of the other religious sciences.” If, however, we continue to read al-Ghaz?l?
we end up with a different interpretation than the one provided by Frank.
Immediately at the point where Frank stops quoting, al-Ghaz?l? goes on to say
that kal?m
[D]istinguishes between the possible, the
necessary and the impossible in regard to Him [God]; it then illustrates that
the principle of action (a?l al-fi‘l)
is possible to Him; that the making of the world is possible; that since it
[the world] is possible then it needs a maker (mu?dith); that the sending of prophets is among His possible
actions and that He is capable of it and of illustrating their truth through
miracles; that this possible [act] is in fact an actual reality. At this point
the speculation of the theologian terminates, and the disposition of the
intellect ends (‘inda h?dha yanqa?i‘u
kal?mu l-mutakallimi wa yantahi ta?arrufu l-‘aql). Indeed, the intellect
only demonstrates the veracity of the prophet. It then absolves itself and it
concedes that it accepts what it receives from the prophet regarding God and
the hereafter. These are things that the intellect neither perceives
independently, nor does it deem them logically impossible; for it is possible
that the law (shar‘) informs of
things that the intellect is incapable of perceiving independently (when left
to its own means).
Frank’s
interpretation of the above quotation fails to note that when al-Ghaz?l? refers
to kal?m as al-‘ilm kull? he does not mean that it is the highest form of
knowledge, but simply that it is the starting point of all sciences, a stratum
which all the sciences share; not a theology but a simple tool. More
importantly, rather than ascribing the highest of authorities to his own brand
of kal?m, al-Ghaz?l? uses a rational
argument to assert the limited authority of reason in religious matters.
Proceeding
to delineate the distinction that al-Ghaz?l? makes between his higher theology
and traditional kal?m, Frank (21-2)
maintains that “[t]hough his language may vary according to context,
al-Ghaz?l?’s intention remains constant.” School kal?m is for “simple people, while the ‘balance’ of truly
demonstrative reasoning, which gives ‘genuine insight into the true realities
of things,’ is for the intellectual elite (Qis??s,
79f.) who are capable of a higher theology which he refers to consistently as
‘‘ilm al-muk?shafah’.” Here too,
Frank’s interpretation does not conform with the general context of the Qis??s. In defining what he means by the
word “balance,” al-Ghaz?l? says (Qis??s,
50-1): “One who weighs gold with a balance can weigh with it silver and other
precious stones, because the balance identifies its quantity not in so much
that it is gold, but because it is a quantity.” Thus, in contrast with Frank’s
interpretation, al-Ghaz?l?’s “balance” is a neutral tool, an instrument, which
provides information about quantities not essences, and which is needed for all
sciences (religious or secular) (Qis??s,
82, also Musta?f?, 10). Needless to
say, an instrument of knowledge does not in itself constitute a theology or a
cosmology.
The
contention that al-Ghaz?l? adopts a cosmology, which is derived from the
cosmological systems of the philosophers, is central to Frank’s argument. He
argues (22-23) that in the I?y?’
(20f.) al-Ghaz?l? considers as part of the religious sciences “the science of
the states of the soul and its moral characteristics, good and bad.” Under
these religious sciences al-Ghaz?l? includes ‘ilm al-mu‘?mala and 'ilm
al-muk?shafa, the former being the “higher ethical science,” while the
later is “a higher theology that embraces the knowledge of the celestial realm,
its governance of the material, sublunary world and its role in accomplishing
the perfection of the human soul; he [al-Ghaz?l?] says that it is “the science
of what is hidden and this is the ultimate of the sciences.” Frank then quotes
a long paragraph from the I?y?’ in
which al-Ghaz?l? defines what he means by 'ilm
al-muk?shafa. This quote from al-Ghaz?l? again illustrates the problematic
and inconclusive nature of Frank’s interpretations. I will thus reproduce
Frank’s translation; in places where the difference significantly affects the
general sense of the quoted paragraph, I will provide in square brackets my own
translations, as well as translations of omitted sections. Al-Ghaz?l? says (I?y?’, 20f.) that 'ilm al-muk?shafa is
an expression that refers to a light that
appears in the soul when it is cleansed and purified of its bad characteristics
(?if?tuh? l-madhm?mah) and from this
light many things are revealed (yankashif)...
to the point that one achieves the true knowledge (ma‘rifah) of God’s being and of His enduring and perfect attributes
and His judgment in creating this world and the next world and the way that He
ordered the next world to this world [and the knowledge of the meaning of
prophethood and prophet, and the meaning of revelation, and the meaning of
Satan] and the knowledge (ma‘rifah)
[sic. ma‘n?, i.e. meaning] of the
word ‘angels’...[and devils, and the manner in which the devils confront man]
and how the angel becomes manifest to prophets and how revelation reaches them
and the knowledge (ma‘rifah) of the
kingdom of the heavens and the earth [and knowledge of the heart] and how the
hosts of angels and devils meet there in conflict... and what it means to
encounter God (the mighty, the Glorious) and to look at His gracious face and
what it means to be near Him and to stop in his [sic. His] proximity and what
it means to attain blessedness (?u??lu [sic. ?u?ul?]l-sa‘?dah) through
the companionship of the High Council and the company of the angels and the
prophets....
While
it is safe to assume that in the above quote al-Ghaz?l? considers 'ilm al-muk?shafa to be the ultimate
science, it is questionable whether he is referring to a “higher theology” as
opposed to simple mysticism or Sufism. Removing references to Satan, and the
clashes of the “soldiers of angels and devils” in the heart would reorient the
argument of al-Ghaz?l? and give the impression that he is referring to the
hierarchical order of being. However, it would indeed be hard to read a
cosmology into the above passage when it is read in its totality. In fact,
further clarification of the meaning of 'ilm
al-muk?shafa is provided in the same passage as al-Ghaz?l? continues:
... and other things the explication of
which takes too long, for after believing in the truth of these matters people
have various positions regarding their meanings.... Thus we mean by 'ilm al-muk?shafa the lifting of the
veil such that the plain truth in these matters becomes clear in such a way
that it will be analogous to eye witnessing which is never in doubt. This is
possible in the essence of man were it not for the accumulation of rust and
maliciousness on the mirror of the heart due to the filth of the (earthly)
world. We only mean by the science of the way of the hereafter the knowledge of
the manner of cleansing this mirror from the filth that [puts a] veil between
it and God, may He be exalted and glorified, and [between it and] His
attributes and actions. Refining and purifying it (the mirror) comes only
through the avoidance of lusts and by following the example of the prophets,
may God’s prayers be upon them.... There is no way to it except through
exercise (riy??a) the details of
which will follow in the relevant section, and through knowledge and learning.
These are the sciences which are not written in books; a person whom God has
blessed with some of it (i.e. this science) does not talk about it except with
people worthy of it, and these are the ones who participate in it by way of
supplication (mush?rik f?hi ‘al? sab?l
al-mudh?kara), and through the methods of secrets (bi ?ar?q al-asr?r), and this is the hidden science....”
It
is thus clear that according to al-Ghaz?l? ‘ilm
al-muk?shafa has to do with purifying the heart by following the example of
prophets. It should be added that prophets, even according to most earnest
advocates of philosophy, do not arrive at certain knowledge through the
systematic application of the rules of logic, but through intuitive knowledge
and with the aid of revelation. Unlike Aristotelian demonstrative proof (‘ilm al-burh?n), the rules of the
science of muk?shafa are not written
in books because it is a practical science not a theoretical one, and because
it depends on worship, self discipline and supplication. There is abundant
evidence throughout the writings of al-Ghaz?l? that illustrate the distinction
he makes between knowledge acquired through demonstrative proof (burh?n) and other kinds of certain
knowledge (yaq?niyy?t). It would
suffice here to mention one additional example from the Mi‘y?r (192), a book which, according to Frank (29), is in plain
“Aristotelian cast.” Al-Ghaz?l? says that “some kinds of certain conviction (al-i‘tiq?d?t al-yaq?niyya) cannot be
made known to another [person] through demonstrative proof (bi-tar?q al-burh?n), unless [such a
person] participates with us in its practice, so that he can share with us in
the knowledge extracted from it (ill?
idh? sh?rakan? f? mum?rasatihi li-yush?rikan? f? al-‘ul?m al-mustaf?da
minhu).” Therefore, Frank’s interpretation of muk?shafa as a higher theology grounded in Aristotelian logic and
Avicennan epistemology seems to be unwarranted. A more likely meaning, which,
incidentally conforms to the conventional use of the term in Arabic, is the
spiritual, mystical knowledge of the Sufis.
In
yet another example, Frank (24-6) argues that, according to one classification
(I?y?’ 3, 15ff.), al-Ghaz?l?
classifies the sciences into rational and religious; the former including the
sciences concerned with the next world (‘ilmun
’ukhraw?) “clearly to be identified with higher metaphysics ('ilm al-muk?shafa)” (Frank, 24). In this
classification, however, al-Ghaz?l? divides the sciences whose locus is the
heart into rational and religious sciences; the former is then further divided
into necessary sciences which we possess but whose source we cannot identify (l? nadr? min ayna ?a?alat), and
acquired sciences, including worldly sciences as well as sciences concerned
with the next world. It thus follows that there is, according to al-Ghaz?l?,
necessary knowledge that is not acquired but created. Frank does not mention
this kind of knowledge and goes on to quote a long passage in which al-Ghaz?l?
pleads “for the essential role of formal logic.” Frank translation of this
passage starts with the following sentence (25): “The things one seeks to know
are not given innately (fi?riyyah)
and cannot be caught save in the net of truths that are already achieved (al-‘ul?mu l-???ilah)....” In the Arabic
original, however, the word (allat?),
which is dropped by Frank, precedes (fi?riyyah).
The exact translation should thus read: “The things one seeks to know which
are not given innately cannot be caught save in the net of sciences already
achieved....” The difference between these two readings is not trivial.
According to al-Ghaz?l?, there are intellectual sciences that are innately
given and necessary, and burh?n is
neither useful nor essential to the acquisition of these sciences. Given this
reading of the above quotes by al-Ghaz?l?, Frank’s assertion that muk?shafa is identical with rational
higher metaphysics cannot be sustained.
In
chapter four, Frank discusses what he considers to be the anti-Ash‘arite texts
of Ghaz?l?, mainly the Fay?al and the
Munqidh,[19] but also the Ilj?m, Maq?ad, Mishk?h, and parts of the I?y?’. According to Frank (77-8) the Fay?al is formally about the criteria
for determining whether an individual is a believer or an unbeliever when
exercising “non-literal interpretation (ta’w?l)
of descriptions of God” in scriptures. However, Frank adds, the ta’w?l al-Ghaz?l? is really concerned
with in this book is “that involving his conception of the operation of the
cosmic system in the deterministic causation of events....” As proof of this
point, Frank says, “This would seem to be... confirmed where in the discussion
(37ff.) of interpretation and exegesis on the basis of the five modes or levels
of the presence of existence (darj?t
al-wuj?d), he cites as examples of the “intellectual level” (al-wuj?d al-‘aql?) the interpretation
of... God’s “hand” as referring to “a spiritual and intellectual hand,” which
is to say, to the intermediate agency of angels (40, 10ff.), just as the Tradition
according to which “the first thing God created was the intellect....”
In
other words, Frank argues that this particular interpretation of “God’s hand”
illustrates al-Ghaz?l?’s real interest, namely to provide a ta’w?l based on his own cosmology. In
this section of the Fay?al (182-3),
however, al-Ghaz?l? provides several acceptable interpretations of God’s
“hand.” These include, for example, the possibility that the word “hand” refers
to either the metaphorical meaning of the “hand,” i.e. “that with which God
strikes and acts, gives and deprives”; or to the pen “with which true knowledge
is inscribed on the tablets of the hearts of prophets and saints”; or to one of
the attributes of God such as His power or something else. Al-Ghaz?l? adds (Fay?al, 186): “The purpose [of listing
these possibilities] is not to validate any of the interpretations, but to know
that each group, irrespective of the extent to which it adheres to the literal
meaning of the text, must still resort to interpretation.” Al-Ghaz?l? then
states the general rule for validating any particular ta’w?l, namely that it should be demonstrated that the literal
interpretation of the text is impossible (q?y?m
al-burh?n ‘al? isti??lat al-??hir) (Fay?al,
187). It seems abundantly clear, therefore, that al-Ghaz?l?’s real interest in
this book is not to promote any particular kind of ta’w?l based on his own cosmological system. Rather, his “real”
purpose is to establish the criteria for distinguishing between belief and
unbelief, and, ultimately, to foster more tolerance amongst Muslims for the
interpretive exercises.
Another
example used by Frank to argue the point of ta’w?l
based on cosmology is al-Ghaz?l?’s discussion in Ilj?m of the meaning of the Qur’?nic reference to God’s “ascending
the throne” (al-istiw?’ ‘al? al-‘arsh).[20] Frank (84) maintains that despite
al-Ghaz?l?’s reference to Sufis in Ilj?m,
“his ta’w?l of “ascends the throne”
(68f.) and his explanation of the degrees of being (107ff.) make it clear that
it is not the claims of mystical experience that are in question, but rather
his own theoretical cosmology and ontology.”
Here
too, the immediate textual context of al-Ghaz?l?’s discussion seems to
contradict Frank’s reading. In the first section (Ilj?m, 68f.) al-Ghaz?l? considers several interpretations of the
expression “ascending the throne.” While Frank considers only one of these
interpretations, and asserts that it reflects al-Ghaz?l?’s own position,
al-Ghaz?l? argues that all of these interpretations are acceptable. Moreover, even
in the one interpretation considered by Frank, al-Ghaz?l? makes it quite clear
that the knower (‘?rif) cannot assert
the veracity of his own interpretation to the exclusion of other ones, and he
can only confirm its possibility (tajw?z).
As for the “degrees of being” (mar?tib
al-wuj?d), Frank’s reference (Ilj?m,
107ff.) is to a section that deals with the question of the eternity of the
Qur’?n. In this section al-Ghaz?l? argues that there are several ways of
referring to the Qur’?n: one can refer to the Qur’?n in itself, in which case
it is eternal; eternity here, according to al-Ghaz?l?, is an attribute of the
essence of the Qur’?n, not to our knowledge of it, nor to what is uttered on
our tongues or written on blank paper. According to al-Ghaz?l?, knowledge,
utterance, and writing of the Qur’?n are all created; thus, it is possible to
say that the Qur’?n is created if what we are referring to is our knowledge,
the utterance, or the writing of the Qur’?n. It is clear, therefore, that
al-Ghaz?l?’s expression “degrees of being” refers to the various ways of
thinking about the Qur’?n, according to which we may say that it is either
created or not created. There is obviously no reference here to any
cosmological hierarchy as Frank argues.
Frank
(93-4) even questions al-Ghaz?l?’s intentions in the Tah?fut al-Fal?sifa, the one book by al-Ghaz?l? that is devoted
completely to a critique of the doctrines of the Muslim philosophers. Frank
maintains that in the beginning of the Mi‘y?r
al-Ghaz?l? states that the “primary purpose” of the book is to “aid the
reader’s understanding of Tah?fut by
introducing him formally to the logic and the technical lexicon of the
fal?sifa.” However, according to Frank, al-Ghaz?l? concludes the book by
stating a different purpose for it, namely that it was written “in order to
show ‘the way to come to the knowledge of the essential natures of things and
to explain the rules of systematic reasoning.’” Frank adds: “What, thus, at the
outset was stated to be the primary purpose of the book is ignored, as he seems
to imply that most of what he has presented he agrees with.” Supposedly, then,
in the beginning the Mi‘y?r
al-Ghaz?l? portrays the book as a neutral exposition of the epistemological
system underlying the Tah?fut; in the
conclusion of the book, however, it becomes clear that he in fact espouses this
epistemology. Ostensibly, this example demonstrates beyond doubt one of Frank’s
main arguments: that, despite his nominal disclaimers, al-Ghaz?l?’s is really
influenced by philosophy. Moreover, this example seems to provide a stark
illustration of what Frank calls the “rhetorical maneuvers” of al-Ghaz?l?.
On
closer examination, however, none of these conclusions can be sustained.
Indeed, at the outset of the Mi‘y?r,
al-Ghaz?l? does state in no ambivalent terms the purposes for writing the book.
He says (Mi‘y?r, 59): “The motive for
composing this book entitled Mi‘y?r
al-‘Ilm is two fold: first, to explain the methods of systematic thinking
and reasoning (tafh?m ?uruq al-fikr
wal-na?ar), and to elucidate the ways of analogies and reflection; for
since the theoretical sciences are not innately and instinctually available and
given, they are no doubt acquired and sought....” Ghaz?l? adds that he
“organized this book as a scale for speculation and reflection, and a balance
for research and contemplation, and for sharpening the mind... so that it
becomes in relation to the evidence of the mind like metrics for poetry. (rattabn? h?dh? al-kit?b mi‘y?ran lil-na?ar
wal-i‘tib?r, wa m?z?nan lil-ba?th wal-iftik?r, wa ?aq?lan lil-dhihn... fa yak?n
bil-nisba li-adillat al-‘uq?l kal-‘ar?? lil-shi‘r)”. Ghaz?l? continues
(60):
The second motivation [for composing the
book] is to explain what was included in the book Tah?fut al-Fal?sifa, for we debated them using their language and
addressed them on the basis of their terminology which they agreed on in logic.
In this book the meanings of these technical words will become clear. This is
the more specific (akha??) of the two
motives, while the first is more general and more important.... As for the
reasons why it is more important, surely there is no need to point this out to
you. As for the reason of it being more general, it is because its benefit
encompasses all the theoretical sciences, intellectual and legal (al-‘aqliyya minh? wal-fiqhiyya), for we
will show you that systematic reasoning in the legal sciences is not different
from that in the intellectual sciences in its organization and conditions and
measures; rather, (they differ) only in the source of their premises (ma’?khidh al-muqaddim?t).
So,
contrary to Frank’s assertions, al-Ghaz?l? does not hide his true intentions in
the beginning of the Mi‘y?r, only to
disclose them at the end. Rather, al-Ghaz?l? is not just consistent, but he is
forthright in expressing his views and intentions right from the outset.
Moreover, in the Mi‘y?r al-Ghaz?l?
does not “formally present the definitions of the fal?sifa” (Frank, 93), but
simply the neutral tool of logic which, according to al-Ghaz?l?, is as useful
for fiqh as it is for any other
rational science.
Al-Ghaz?l?’s
most tangible and most unequivocal condemnation of philosophical doctrine is
related to the question of resurrection. According to Frank (91), “the only
instance... al-Ghaz?l? seems manifestly to deny what he in fact believes occurs
in the discussion of resurrection in Iqti??d.”
Frank adds (95-6), however, that al-Ghaz?l? expresses his “obvious commitment
to the psychology and metaphysics of the fal?sifa,” in his discussion in the M?z?n[21] of the status of the soul after death,
and that “al-Ghaz?l? appears to agree with the thesis, here attributed to ‘the
Sufis and the metaphysicians amongst the fal?sifa,’ that at death the soul
becomes permanently separated from the body: the pleasures and pains of the
next life are purely intellectual, those depicted in the revelation being only
images for what cannot be imagined (5f.).” Now since this is perhaps Frank’s
most radical reinterpretation of al-Ghaz?l?, I will quote the full reference
from the M?z?n (5-6) before
addressing Frank’s argument:
Regarding the afterlife people are
divided into four groups: One group believes in (the day of) congregation and
resurrection of the dead, and in paradise and hell just as the scriptures have
spelled it out, and as the Qur’?n has clearly described it (kam? na?aqat bihi al-shar?’i‘ wa af?a?a ‘an
wa?fihi al-Qur’?n). They confirm the bodily pleasures relating to
intercourse, food, smells, touch, dress, and views. They also acknowledge that
in addition to these there are kinds of happiness and varieties of pleasures
which the description of the describers cannot encompass, for they are things
that no eye has seen and no ear has heard of and never even occurred to the
heart of a human. [They also believe] that all of this goes on without
interruption, and that it can only be attained through knowledge and actions.
These are the totality of the Muslims (wa
h?’ul?’ hum al-Muslim?n k?ffa), and indeed most of the followers of
prophets among Jews and Christians.
The
second group, are some of the Muslim metaphysicians among the philosophers who
acknowledge a kind of pleasure the manner of which does not occur to the heart
of human, and they call it intellectual pleasure. As for the sensible
(pleasures), they deny their external existence but confirm them through
imagination as in the state of sleep... except that sleep is unsettled by
waking up while (pleasure) is everlasting and is never unsettled. They claim (za‘am?) that this sort of thing is
confirmed for those who are fond of sensible pleasures and the attention of
whose souls is fixated on them, and who do not rise to intellectual pleasures.
This (opinion) too, does not lead to a state which entails slackness in the
quest (wa h?dh? l? yuf?? il? amr y?jib
fut?ran fil-?alab)....
A
third group went as far as denying sense pleasures altogether, by way of
reality or by way of imagination. They claim that imagination does not occur
except through bodily instruments, while death severs the connection between
the soul and the body which is its instrument for imagination and for the rest
of the senses, and it never returns to govern the body once it discards it.
Thus nothing remains for it (the soul) except pains and pleasures that are not
sensibles.... They also claim that the senses in regard to the pleasures which
exist in the abode of the afterlife are extremely inadequate.... They also
claim that since this (intellectual pleasure) is far from the understanding of
the masses, they (i.e. the pleasures of the afterlife) are compared for them
with what they are familiar with of the sensibles.... This (opinion) too, had
it been correct, does not entail slackness in the quest.... This is the opinion
of the Sufis and the metaphysicians among the philosophers... in fact the
highest echelons of the Sufis openly profess (this view) and say that whoever
worships God to seek paradise or to avoid hell is mean. Rather, the aim of the
travelers to God is nobler than this....
(12)
...And the Sufis and the philosophers who believe in God and the hereafter in
general, even if they disagree on the manner, all agree that happiness is in
knowledge and deeds (al-‘ilm wal-‘amal). They only speculate over the specifics
of knowledge and deeds. So to hold back despite this agreement is
foolishness....
(13)
...Suffice it for you to embark on [the acquisition of] knowledge and [the
performance of good] deeds on which all three [groups] agree, since your
purpose in asking is not disputation, but your purpose is to seek success, just
like a patient who seeks a cure without disputation, for his goal is the
agreement of various physicians on it.
If
language and choice of words is any indication, as Frank argues throughout his
book, then certainly al-Ghaz?l? is not in favor of the position that Frank
attributes to him. Al-Ghaz?l? refers to those who believe in bodily
resurrection as the “totality of the Muslims,” and as those whose belief is
“just as the scriptures have spelled it out, and as the Qur’?n has clearly
described it.” As for the two other groups, al-Ghaz?l? uses the term “they
claim” several times to refer to their doctrines; he also uses the phrase “had
it been true” to refer to the doctrine of the third group. Rather than implying
an open endorsement, as Frank maintains, al-Ghaz?l? seems to express hesitation
even as he reports the views of these groups. Frank also suggests that
al-Ghaz?l?’s use of the adjective Islamic in reference to the “metaphysicians
amongst the fal?sifa” means that he advocates their view. There are, however,
two groups of such metaphysicians whom al-Ghaz?l? describes as Islamic; since
the positions of these two groups are significantly different, al-Ghaz?l? could
not have agreed with both and, therefore, no deeper meaning can be read into
his use of the adjective “Islamic.” Rather than dismissing al-Ghaz?l?’s clear
position on resurrection as stated not only in the Iqti??d, but also in the Fay?al,
Tah?fut, and elsewhere, the one
obvious interpretation of the above quotation from the M?z?n seems to reaffirm this position. Al-Ghaz?l?’s purpose is not
to discuss which of the different positions on life after death is correct, but
simply to point out the consensus among all schools, even those with whom he
disagrees, that there is life after death, and that it is necessary to do good
deeds and to acquire knowledge in preparation for this afterlife.
Al-Ghaz?l?
on Causation
The
cosmology of al-Ghaz?l?, according to Frank, parallels that of Ibn S?n? in its
conception of a definite cosmic hierarchy with a system of deterministic,
invariable secondary causes.[22] In this system God governs the universe
through intermediaries (angel, intellect, or outermost sphere), and He cannot
disrupt the operation of secondary causes. Since this argument is not prevalent
in scholarship on al-Ghaz?l?, Frank devotes large sections of this book to
demonstrate that there is in fact an invariant, sequential relationship between
cause and effect in the writings of al-Ghaz?l?. He also tries to prove that
al-Ghaz?l?’s use of traditional Ash‘arite language is simply to appease his
Ash‘arite readers and to conceal his true sympathy with philosophical
determinism. Thus, according to Frank, al-Ghaz?l?’s use of such standard
Ash‘arite expressions as God’s custom is purely rhetorical, while in reality he
believes in the invariability of the relationship between cause and effect.
A
central example which Frank uses to demonstrate the above argument is
al-Ghaz?l?’s discussion of causation in the Mi‘y?r
(109, 21ff.). In his treatment of the nature of the relationship between
decapitation and death al-Ghaz?l? presents two alternative explanations without
indicating his preference: either the “connection between the two events is
something necessary and whose alteration, therefore, is impossible absolutely,”
or that “the connection between the two is simply “the normal course of God’s
custom (jaray?nu sunnati ll?h)
through the efficacy of His eternal will, which is not subject to substitution
and alterations” (Frank, 18). In either case, what matters, according to Frank,
is that “the invariance of the connection between decapitation and death is
inevitable” (19).
Al-Ghaz?l?
gives the example above in the course of responding to one who questions the
certainty of the belief in an invariant relationship between decapitation and
death. A questioner repeats the traditional Ash‘arite argument that
decapitation is not the cause of death, eating not the cause of satiation, and
fire not the cause of burning; rather, God habitually creates burning, death,
and satiation together with these things but not because of them. The full
response by al-Ghaz?l? reads:
We have pointed out the profundity and
the true meaning of this subject in the book Tah?fut al-Fal?sifa (qad
nabbahn? ‘al? ghawr h?dh? al-fa?l wa ?aq?qatihi f? kit?b Tah?fut
al-Fal?sifa). The extent that is needed now is that, if a speaker is told
that his son has been decapitated, he would not doubt his death, and there is
no rational person who would doubt it; he would admit the occurrence of death
and look into the mode of connection. As for the speculation over whether it
[i.e. the connection between the two events] is a necessary concomitance, which
is impossible to change, or whether it is by virtue of the normal course of
God’s custom through the efficacy of His eternal will, which is not subject to
substitution or alteration, this is a speculation over the mode of
concomitance, not the [fact of] concomitance itself. So understand this, and
let it be known that to doubt the death of a decapitated person is mere
delusion, and that the believe in his death is a certainty regarding which one entertains
no doubts.”
The
first important point is that, on the nature of the connection between cause
and effect, al-Ghaz?l? refers his reader to the Tah?fut, where, in conformity with Ash‘arite occasionalism, he
clearly states that the relationship is one of habitual concomitance in accord
with God’s custom. Al-Ghaz?l? consistently refers to the Tah?fut every time the question of the relationship between causes
and effects comes up. For example, as in the case with the above example from
the Mi‘y?r, almost identical
references are made in the Mi?akk
(61), and the Musta?f? (45-6). It is
also significant that in these three examples, the discussion occurs when
al-Ghaz?l? lists the various methods of attaining certain knowledge (mad?rik al-yaq?n), and, in particular,
when he discusses what he alternatively calls ‘tajr?biyy?t’
(experience) or ‘mujray?t’ (God’s
regular custom). Therefore, in the example quoted by Frank, al-Ghaz?l? does not
address the mode of the connection between cause and effect; on this question
he is abundantly clear, and he consistently refers his readers to the Tah?fut on this issue. Surely one cannot
expect al-Ghaz?l?, or anyone else, to make all of his arguments in every single
book he writes, and unambivalent reference should suffice to indicate his
position on this matter. The subject of the above quote from al-Ghaz?l? is the
methods of attaining certain knowledge; such knowledge, according to
al-Ghaz?l?, is not contingent on a particular mode of connection between cause
and effect. Rather, it suffices that there are habitual regularities in the
relationships between events, a condition which is easily satisfied under the
traditional Ash‘arite notion of God’s custom.
Building
on his analysis of the example of decapitation in the Mi‘y?r, Frank moves on to argue that the ambiguity in this
discussion can be resolved if interpreted in light of al-Ghaz?l?’s cosmology.
Frank (19-20, also 84) quotes a section from the Ilj?m, which he considers to be an “exposition of the deterministic
governance of the world through the angel of the outermost sphere.” Frank
argues that “in Ilj?m (68f.) he
[al-Ghaz?l?] offers the relationship between the brain and the rest of the body
as an analogue to the relation of the outermost sphere to the rest of the
created universe, and there states his position clearly and unambiguously: the
soul governs the body through the brain and although it is possible absolutely
that man have been created such that it governs the body in some other way,
what God wills he wills eternally and necessarily. It is de facto impossible
that God have willed that the soul be related to the body in any other way,
wherefore man is, in effect, so constituted that it is impossible that the soul
govern the body other than through the instrumentality of the brain. Here (Ilj?m, 69, 6) al-Ghaz?l? cites Fa?ir (v. 43) verbatim in confirmation
of his thesis: ‘you shall never find any substitution in the custom of God.’”
Again,
for a proper interpretation of the quote above, we will need to examine its
immediate textual context. In the previous section of the Ilj?m, al-Ghaz?l? discusses various ways of interpreting scriptures;
after going over several kinds of forbidden interpretations, he considers the
interpretation which is done by a knowledgeable person (‘?rif) for himself. Here al-Ghaz?l? lists three kinds: the first is
definite or certain; the second is uncertain; and the third is one of which the
interpreter is almost certain but not completely so (ma?n?nan ?annan gh?liban); this means that he knows for sure that
the interpretation is logically possible, but he is not sure whether this
particular interpretation is the one intended by God. This last kind is
involved when interpreting the expression “ascending the throne” (al-istiw?’ ‘al? al-‘arsh) to mean the
special attribution (al-nisba al-kh???a)
of the throne; namely “that God administers the whole universe and governs
matters from the heavens to the earth through the throne; for He does not
create in the world a form unless He creates it in the throne, in the same way
a sculpturer or a scribe does not create a form or a word on a white (paper)
unless he creates it in the brain.... Thus, the heart governs the matters of
its world, which is its body, through the brain” (Ilj?m, 69). Al-Ghaz?l? goes on to say:
Perhaps we hesitate over whether positing
this relation (nisba) of the throne
to God, may He be exalted, is possible, either because it is necessary in
itself, or because He made it the normal course of His custom and habit, even
though its opposite is not impossible, in the same way He made the normal
course of His custom with regard to the heart of man that he [i.e. man] cannot
govern except through the brain, even though it is logically possible with
regard to God that He could have enabled him [i.e., man to govern the body]
without the brain, had His eternal will ordained it, and had the eternal word
which is His knowledge truly determined it. Thus, its opposite becomes
impossible not on account of any deficiency in the essence of power (dh?t al-qudra), but because of the
impossibility of anything that contradicts the eternal will and the
pre-existent eternal knowledge, and this is why He said: “you shall never find
any change in the custom of God”; it does not change because it is necessary,
and its necessity is because it issues from a necessary eternal will, and the
consequence of the necessary is itself necessary; furthermore, its opposite is
impossible, even though it is not impossible in itself, but on account of something
else, namely that it would lead to replacing eternal knowledge with ignorance,
and it would declare impossible the execution of Divine will.
Al-Ghaz?l?
then repeats his warning that, although this kind of interpretation of the
meaning of the throne and its relation to God is logically possible, upon
reflection one continues to wonder whether this relation does in fact exist in
reality. Al-Ghaz?l? adds that in all events, the speculator (n??ir) should not rest assured that his
interpretation is final and certain, and that he should only make definitive
statements regarding his own preferences and choices, and not the true meaning
of the text which he can never know for certain.
Now,
Frank rightly maintains that, according to al-Ghaz?l?, “it is not possible that
God have willed that this [i.e., decapitation resulting in death] not be the
case”; Frank’s other conclusions, however, do not necessarily follow. According to al-Ghaz?l?, it is
impossible that something happens when God wills otherwise. God does not will
one thing and then act in a way that is different from what He willed. This,
however, does not mean that God is not capable of willing a natural pattern
with habitual relationships between concomitant events, and with occasional
interruptions of this pattern. Put differently, God, in His eternal will, may
ordain one custom, which entails both a customary, recurrent pattern of
relationships between certain events, and a certain number of interruptions of
this pattern. The only thing here that is impossible is that God’s will be
opposed, and thus the natural order of things can be interrupted if God has so
willed. It is significant that
al-Ghaz?l? repeatedly states that the invariance in the connection between
events is not inherent in things on account of their natures, and that only
God’s will is invariant. This reading seems to be confirmed by al-Ghaz?l?’s
emphatic assertion of the uncertain nature of the interpretation that God
governs the universe through the throne. While Frank considers this to be
al-Ghaz?l?’s own position, al-Ghaz?l? is keen on indicating that such an
interpretation is permissible (j?’iz)
but not certain (qa?‘?). Moreover,
al-Ghaz?l? argues that while the governance of the head over the body is known,
there is no certain parallel in the case of the universe; therefore, it is not
as clear as Frank argues that there is a cosmology in the thought of al-Ghaz?l?
that neatly ties the “outermost sphere” and the sublunary world.
In
his chapter on the Iqti??d, Frank
(38-9) argues that al-Ghaz?l?’s use of “God’s custom” is incompatible with the
traditional Ash‘arite use. According to the Ash‘arites, God’s custom means the
“normal and sometimes invariant sequence of events in an occasionalistic
universe,” whereas it “is employed by Ghaz?l? to describe the lawful operation
of secondary causes in a deterministic universe willed and created by God.”
Frank (44-46) goes on to argue that in the Iqti??d,
al-Ghaz?l? does not commit himself to traditional Ash‘arite occasionalism and
that, in fact, even in this book, one can read a Ghaz?lian cosmology according
to which “God creates through a series of secondary causes....” Neither does
al-Ghaz?l?, according to Frank, commit himself to the traditional Ash‘arite
position on the relationship (or lack thereof) between action and the created
power of voluntary action. Frank says (44, quoting Iqti??d, 92): “All of this [discussion of human voluntary act as
performance (kasb)] sounds very much
like traditional Ash‘arite teaching. Had he said ‘lam yaqi‘’ [sic. yaqa‘]
or ‘lam ya??ul bi-qudrati l-‘abd’, it
might be difficult to understand him to intend anything else, but, as it is,
his intention is not fully and explicitly stated.” Al-Ghaz?l?, adds Frank (46),
“nowhere unambiguously commits himself to the thesis of al-Juwayn? that the
action “does not take place through the created power of voluntary action.”
Elsewhere, Frank (90) restates his thesis and adds that when the question of
“the nature and efficacy of the created power of voluntary action” is raised
“al-Ghaz?l? tends to weasel,” and “When he is formally obliged to deal with the
question in Iqti??d, he buries the
real issue under a cloud of dialectical obfuscation.”
The
evidence from the Iqti??d, however,
does not accord with these conclusions. To start with, in taking up the example
of decapitation in which, according to Frank, causal determinism and cosmology
are inevitable, al-Ghaz?l? (Iqti??d,
224) maintains that ultimately the solution of this problem is to be sought in
the “general rule regarding the pervasiveness of [God’s] power and the denial
of generation (al-q?n?n
al-ladh? dhakarn?hu f? ‘um?m al-qudra wa ib??l al-tawallud). Based on
this, one should say regarding a person who has been killed that he died by his
ajal (m?ta bi ajalihi), ajal
being the time on which God has created his death, whether or not this (occurs)
with decapitation, lunar eclipse, or the falling of rain; this is because, to
us, all of these are concomitants and not generated acts, but the concomitance
of some of them is repeated by custom and some are not repeated (li’anna kulla h?dhihi ‘indan? muqtarin?t wa
laysat mutawallid?t, wa l?kin iqtir?n ba’?ih? yatakarraru bi al-‘?da, wa
ba‘?ih? l? yatakarraru).” Frank dismisses this clear rejection by
al-Ghaz?l? of tawallud, and his
obvious endorsement of occasionalism.
Frank
also contends that al-Ghaz?l?’s “intention is not fully and clearly stated”
when he talks about human voluntary act as performance. Al-Ghaz?l?, according
to Frank, uses ambivalent language, but does not commit himself to the
traditional Ash‘arite position on this issue; had he used the unambiguous
expressions (lam yaqa‘) and (lam ya??ul), it “might be difficult to
understand him to intend anything else.” Now, it so happens, that al-Ghaz?l?
uses exactly these two expressions just a few paragraphs after the section
quoted by Frank. Thus in the Iqti??d
(94-5), in response to one who maintains that “a created power through which an
action does not take place (qudra l?
yaqa‘ bih? maqd?r) is equivalent to impotence,” al-Ghaz?l? says: “if
you mean that it [qudra] is equivalent to impotence in that the action
did not happen by it (f? anna al-maqd?r lam
yaqa‘ bih?), then your assertion is correct....” Ghaz?l? later says
(98) “Therefore, according to us it is impossible to say that an action took
place through a created power ‘of voluntary action’ (fa inn? idhan a?aln? an naq?l ?a?ala maqd?r bi qudra ??ditha).”
Here too, both in substance and in language, al-Ghaz?l? conforms to traditional
Ash‘arism, and the contentions that he “tends to weasel” and “buries the real
issue under a cloud of dialectical obfuscation,” are, to say the least,
unfounded.
In
yet another example, Frank argues (94) that the Mi?akk marks “an important moment in al-Ghaz?l?’s career,” in which
he presents “his own theology in his own terms.” This is so because al-Ghaz?l?,
according to Frank (94), speaks of “God’s governance of the universe through
the agency of a “single celestial cause” by means of a complex sequence of
intermediary causes” (Mi?akk, 82).
Now,
this quotation is from a section where al-Ghaz?l? discusses physiognomy (fir?sa); he says:
All indicants (adilla) in physiognomy are such that one draws conclusions
regarding the character on the basis of appearance and mood, not because one is
the cause of the other; rather, both, according to the normal course of custom
(bi-?ukm jaray?n al-‘?da) are the
results of one cause.... Thus it becomes known that one implies the other upon
(fulfilling) other conditions which are added to it.... It is also known for a
certainty that the redness on the shoulders of sheep is not the cause of the
fighting of sultans.... Rather, it is not unlikely that, as part of the wonders
of the creations of God, may He be exalted, there exists among the heavenly
causes a single cause that happens to occur in that particular year (yattafiq f? tilka al-sana) which
would be at once the cause, according to the normal course of custom, for a
certain life in the members of animals and their formations, and in the causes
of abundance of clouds, and in the ferocity of hearts, which are the causes of
fighting.... These sciences (physiognomy) are only denied by ignorant people
who have no knowledge of the wonders of God’s creations, may He be exalted, and
the expanse of His power.
Once
again, Frank’s interpretation of the quote above seems improbable when
considered in the context of the whole passage where it occurs. First, it is
significant that the subject that al-Ghaz?l? treats in the above passage is
physiognomy, which may be derivative, but hardly representative of a cosmology
influenced by philosophy. Second, al-Ghaz?l?’s emphatic reference to the
traditional Ash‘arite notion of custom (jary?n
al-‘?da) clearly attributes effective causation to God. Finally, when
al-Ghaz?l? speaks of “a single heavenly (or celestial) cause” he obviously does
not mean a fixed celestial cause (such as an angel, or intellect) in a
permanent system of cosmological hierarchies; for, not only does al-Ghaz?l? say
that this “celestial cause” is an accidental event that happens to be connected
at one particular moment (yattafiq
f? tilka al-sana) to a number of other events, but he also says that
it functions as a cause by virtue of custom (bi-?ukm ijr?’ al-‘?da). So, rather than providing evidence for
al-Ghaz?l?’s belief in the deterministic operation of intermediary secondary
causes, the above reference from the Mi?akk
seems to illustrate his adherence to traditional Ash‘arite occasionalism.
Conclusions
Frank
is justified in arguing that al-Ghaz?l? criticizes and differs from traditional
kal?m, and that he does not think it
represents the highest form of knowing. Frank also rightly argues that
al-Ghaz?l?’s standard kal?m works do
not include a full exposition of his views on all subject matters. It does not
follow, however, that these works do not reflect al-Ghaz?l?’s “fuller
understanding” of the subjects he does address in these books. In other words,
al-Ghaz?l? may not say everything he knows in each and every book he writes,
but what he says he means. Perhaps, it would be useful to use as a principle
for interpreting al-Ghaz?l?, a rule which he himself repeats in various places
in his work, namely, that unless one can demonstrate that a statement taken
literally is impossible, one has to accept it as it is. While Frank’s analysis
of the technical terminology employed by al-Ghaz?l? provides some useful
insights into his thought, it often proves to be precarious. For example, Frank
(72) points out that, in his proof of the contingency of the world and the
existence of God in the Iqti??d,
al-Ghaz?l? “expressly points the reader toward the Avicennan ontology, which he
considers the proper conceptual foundation for a truly demonstrative proof....”
By “Avicennan ontology” Frank presumably means the reference to various kinds
of being (wuj?d). But, what Frank
misses here, however, is that despite his use of Avicennan idiom, al-Ghaz?l? is
still trying to prove the contingency of the world, contrary to one of the most
basic doctrines of the philosophers.
The
problems that, in our view, Frank could not resolve by analysis of al-Ghaz?l?’s
terminology, may be better addressed through examination of his general
intellectual program. Rather than assuming a hidden agenda every time we
encounter some ambivalence or possible ambiguity in his writings, it may be
more profitable to grant that al-Ghaz?l? is trying to be consistent, but he is
dealing with intertwined and at times conflicting epistemologies and systems of
knowledge. The idea of gnostic knowledge (al-ma‘?rif
al-kashfiyya) is one area where there is possible contradiction in the
thought of al-Ghaz?l?. He tries to prove the validity of this kind of knowledge
by using logical arguments, and his language betrays the influence on his
thought of the philosophical metaphysics of an assortment of various schools of
philosophy. And yet, al-Ghaz?l? continues to attack philosophy and to repudiate
its metaphysics. Therefore, as I argued above, it does not follow that
al-Ghaz?l? means by 'ilm al-muk?shafa
a “higher theology” that is based on Aristotelian demonstrative proof. Rather,
the fundamental tension in the abstract thought of al-Ghaz?l? derives from the
very fact that he tries to use logical reasoning to demonstrate the limited
authority of reason. Arguably, this is one of the central objectives of the
Ash‘arites. In fact, when read in the context of his general ideology,
al-Ghaz?l? exhibits remarkable consistency in his unwavering commitment to
traditional Ash‘arism.
Rather
than being nominally committed to the Ash‘arite position on account of
training, professional interests, old connections, and other factors that have
no bearing on his real beliefs, al-Ghaz?l?’s commitment to Ash‘arism is much
more serious than Frank concedes. Frank overlooks what is perhaps the most
important ideological dimension that guides al-Ghaz?l?’s intellectual career.
At the time of al-Ash‘ar? (d. 935 AD), the priorities of the school doctrine
were to establish the importance of kal?m
against the objections of the ?anbalites, and to formulate a unified and
acceptable Sunni theology as distinct from that of the Mu‘tazilites. This focus
starts to shift way before al-Ghaz?l?’s time, certainly by the time of ‘Abd
al-Q?hir al-Baghd?d? (d. 429 AH/1037 AD). Al-Baghd?d? delineates a new set of
Ash‘arite priorities in his Al-Farq bayn
al-Firaq[23] (282) where he singles out the Ism?‘?li
B??iniyya as the greatest enemy of Sunni Islam; he says:
Know, may God please you, that the harm
of the B??iniyya to the various groups (firaq)
of Muslims is greater than the harm of Jews and Christians and Maj?s; in fact it is greater than the
harm of the Dahriyya and the rest of
the kinds of unbelievers; even greater than the harm of the false Messiah who
will appear at the end of time. [This is so] because those who will be led
astray by the summons of the B??iniyya, from the time they appeared till our
present day, are far more numerous than those who are led astray by the false
Messiah at the time of his appearance; for the strife of the false (Messiah)
will not last more than forty days, while the slanders of the B??iniyya (fa??’i? al-B??iniyya) are more numerous
than the sand and rain drops.
Al-Ghaz?l?
clearly commits himself to this Ash‘arite program. In fact, with al-Ghaz?l? the
political attack against B??iniyya gains an elaborate theoretical dimension.
For him, the struggle against the B??iniyya is not just over political or even
theological issues; rather it is a fight over the authority and role of reason.
It is significant that al-Ghaz?l? (Fay?al,
195) says that differences on the principle of the im?mate, its designation and
its conditions do not justify the charge of unbelief. Therefore, the Ism?‘?lis
are not accused of unbelief on account of their doctrine of the imamate;
rather, they attribute lying to the prophet, a fact that is itself an outcome
of their arbitrary ta’w?l of
scriptures, and their suspension of the role of reason in distinguishing
between right and wrong in matters of religion. In the face of the Ism?‘?li
belief that the imam has a monopoly over the secret knowledge of the scripture,
al-Ghaz?l? insists on the role of logic as the shared method for acquiring
knowledge.
Al-Ghaz?l?,
then, remains committed to the general Ash‘arite objective of securing an
authoritative role for the rational faculties against the B??iniyya who reject
this authority. Al-Ghaz?l?, however, is keen to distinguish his position from
those who go as far as judging or even dismissing the scriptural authority on
the basis of human reason. This distinction is repeated over and over again in
almost all of the works of al-Ghaz?l?; for example, in the section quoted above
from the Musta?f? (5-6) al-Ghaz?l?
maintains that, if something cannot be demonstrated through burh?n, then it does not follow that it
is impossible; rather “the intellect only demonstrates the truthfulness of the
prophet and then absolves itself (ya‘zilu
nafsahu),” and concedes the higher authority of the scripture.
Consistent
with this theoretical attack on the B??iniyya, al-Ghaz?l? also identifies
philosophy as the source for the strong and deadly (as it were) theoretical
underpinnings of Ism?‘?li ideology. Distorted as the Ism?‘?li views of
philosophy may have been, al-Ghaz?l?’s censure of the metaphysics of the
philosophers is in effect an attack on the Ism?‘?li B??iniyya. In Fa??’i? al-B??iniyya[24] (46), for example, al-Ghaz?l? says in
reference to the b??ini belief
regarding the hereafter (ma‘?d):
“This is their opinion (madhhab)
regarding the hereafter; it is exactly the opinion of the philosophers. It only
became widespread among them (the B??iniyya) when a group of dualists and
philosophers dedicated themselves to the support of their madhhab.... Thus most of their madhhab
conformed to the dualists and the philosophers in secret (b??in) while it conformed with the other Raw?fi? and Sh?‘a in
outward appearance (??hir).”
Al-Ghaz?l? makes similar remarks when referring to the b??in? doctrine of prophethood which is “close to the madhhab of the philosophers” (40) and is
“extracted from the madh?hib of the
philosophers on prophethood with some distortion and change” (42).
There
is, then, in the various writings of al-Ghaz?l? a consistent commitment to
traditional Ash‘arism, not just at the level of ideology, but also at the level
of the deeper theoretical conceptions and objectives. In the same reference
quoted in the beginning of this essay, Ibn Taymiyya attributes discrepancies in
the thought of al-Ghaz?l? to his excessive eagerness to acquire knowledge, and
not to the lack of the proper tools to do so. Frank, in another divergence from
Ibn Taymiyya, is not as generous in his assessment; after carefully reading
al-Ghaz?l?, Frank (92) concludes that “his formal treatment of a number of
topics is remarkably superficial.” However, the evidence provided by Frank to
substantiate his allegation is not incontrovertible. Although Frank does not
claim to have said the last word on the subject, he does aim at providing a
“useful basis for further investigation” (101) of al-Ghaz?l? by establishing
the exact nature of his relationship with traditional Ash‘arism. In this book,
therefore, Professor Frank simply tries to pin al-Ghaz?l? down. The great
thinker, however, remains at large.
* This is a review article of R. M. Frank,
Al-Ghaz?l? and the Ash‘arite School.
Duke Monographs in Medieval and Renaissance Studies 15. Durham and London: Duke
University Press, 1994. 101.
[1] Mu?ammad al-Mawl? Mu?sin al-K?sh?n? Ibn
al-Murta??, al-Ma?ajja al-Bay??’ f?
Tahdh?b Kit?b al-I?y?’ (Tehran, 1960).
[2] See, for example, Miguel Asin Palacios, Algazel: dogmatic, moral, ascetica (Zaragoza,
1901).
[3] M. Watt, for example, argues that since
the contradiction between the third section of Mishk?t al-Anw?r and the rest of the book, as well as al-Ghaz?l?’s
other books, amounts to real incompatibility, therefore, this section could not
have been written by al-Ghaz?l?. See M. Watt, “A Forgery in al-Ghaz?l?’s
Mishk?t?” Journal of the Royal Asiatic
Society (1949): 5-22. Also see Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Mishk?t al-Anw?r, ed. A. ‘Af?f? (Cairo, 1964).
[4] A?mad Ibn Taymiyya, Majm?‘ Fat?w? Shaykh al-Isl?m A?mad ibn Taymiyya, ed. Mu?ammad ibn
Q?sim al-Ԥ?im? al-Najd? al-?anbal?, 37 vols. (Saudi Arabia, 1977), 4: 63-6.
[5] In the above mentioned article, Watt
similarly dismisses the notion that contradictions between various parts of
al-Ghaz?l?’s works can be explained by dividing them into esoteric and
exoteric, or by arguing that certain esoteric writings are exclusively
addressed to the intellectual elite. Unlike Watt, however, Frank does not
consider the possibility that certain works are falsely attributed to
al-Ghaz?l?, and argues instead that, in general, the noted contradictions in
the works of al-Ghaz?l? are apparent (at the level of language) and are not
real.
[6] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Fay?al al-Tafriqa bayn al-Isl?m wal-Zandaqa,
ed. S. Duny? (Cairo, 1961).
[7] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Ilj?m al-‘Aw?m ‘an ‘Ilm al-kal?m, ed. M.
Baghd?d? (Beirut, 1985).
[8] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Tah?fut al-Fal?sifa, ed. M. Bouyges
(Beirut, 1982).
[9] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Mi‘y?r al-‘Ilm, ed. S. Duny? (Cairo:
1961).
[10] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Mi?akk al-Na?ar, ed. M. B. al-Na‘s?n?
(Beirut, 1966).
[11] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Al-Musta?f? min ‘Ilm al-U??l, 2 vols.
(B?l?q, 1322 A.H).
[12] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Al-Maq?ad al-Asn? f? Shar? Ma‘?n? Asm?’
All?h al-?usn?, ed. Fadlou A. Shehadi (Beirut, 1986).
[13] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, I?y?’ ‘Ul?m al-D?n, 4 vols. (Beirut,
1982).
[14] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Jaw?hir al-Qur’?n (Beirut, 1977).
[15] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Al-Arba‘?n f? U??l al-D?n, (Cairo,
1925).
[16] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Al-Qis??s al-Mustaq?m, ed. Victor
Shal?at (Beirut, 1983).
[17] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Al-Iqti??d f? al-I‘tiq?d, ed. I. A.
Cubukcu and H Atay (Ankara, 1962).
[18] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Al-Ris?la al-Qudsiyya, ed. A. L. Tibawi,
in The Islamic Quarterly 9.3-4
(1965): 79-94.
[19] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Al-Munqidh min al-?al?l, ed. J. Saliba
and K. ‘Ayy?d (Beirut, 1983).
[20] for further discussion see the section
below on causation.
[21] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, M?z?n al-‘Amal (Cairo, 1963).
[22] This argument is fully articulated in
Frank’s earlier work Creation and the
Cosmic System: al-Ghaz?l? and Avicenna (Heidelberg: Carl Winter
Universitatsverlag, 1992). For a review of this work see Michael E. Marmura,
“Ghaz?lian Causes and Intermediaries,” JAOS
115.1 (1995): 89-100.
[23] ‘Abd al-Q?hir ibn ??hir ibn Mu?ammad
Al-Baghd?d?, Al-Farq bayn al-Firaq,
ed. M. M. ‘Abd al-?am?d (Cairo, 1964).
[24] Ab? ??mid al-Ghaz?l?, Fa??’i? al-B??iniyya, ed. A. Badawi
(Cairo, 1964).
E-mail:
webmaster
- Sign the Guest Book
Page Information:
Acceptable use policy.
This site was last updated on: 2007-06-06.
This site is constantly being updated since July 2001. This site has been permanently relocated from www.muslimphilosophy.com/gz/articles/Ghazali-Dallal-enh.htm as of February 2004.
© Copyright by Ahmad S. Dallal. Site Copyright 2004 by Al-Ghazali Study Group, ltd. All rights reserved. A not-for-profit organization dedicated to academic study of Imam Ghazali and his works. Individual content may have its own individual copyrights. See copyright information.